
Kant’s theory (1993), emotivism (Stevenson, 1944),
intuitionism (Ross, 1930), the theory of information
ethics (Floridi, 1999) and virtue ethics. Of these
theories we selected utilitarianism, virtue ethics,
intuitionism (Ross’ prima-facie principles), Kant’s
ethics and Rawls theory of justice (“veil of
ignorance”). By taking this selection, we aimed to
offer students a variety of thinking-tools together
with knowledge of the major traditions in ethics.
Students were lectured on the basics of ethics
theories using the following moral conflict as an
example: A friend asked a student if he would lend
him the installation diskette of a text processing
software program so that he could install it in his
own computer. The friend is also a student and he is
about to fail a course he is taking if he does not
complete a given assignment in time.
Utilitarianism. Utilitarianism, originally
developed by Bentham and Mill, holds that an act
that produces the greatest happiness for greatest
number of people, measured in terms of ‘pleasure’
and ‘absence of pain’, is a morally right action. With
respect to the example given above, utilitarianism
then counts which alternative produces a greater
increase in happiness (and pain): loaning the
diskette, or not loaning the diskette. If loaning the
software produces more happiness for the lender and
his friend than negative consequences (pain) to the
software manufacturer, then the act of copying is
acceptable in the light of theory of utilitarianism.
Kant’s ethics. Kant’s ethics can be summarized
by his categorical imperative consisting of the thesis
of universality (i.e., act only on maxims that you
would want to be universal laws), and the rule of
human dignity (always treat other people as an end,
never only as a means). To give a simple example of
how Kant’s universality thesis can be applied to the
case in question, we should ask whether we would
want like to live in society where the copying of SW
is allowed. If we answer in the affirmative, then
copying of SW is acceptable in the light of Kant’s
universality thesis and the student could lend the
software to his friend.
Intuitionism: Ross’ prima-facie principles.
According to the theory of prima-facie duties (Ross,
1930), humans have many such duties, which are
more or less incumbent on us. On some occasions,
those duties make conflicting demands on us and we
have to determine, which of those duties is the more
incumbent on us. In the example case, the student
has duties towards his friend, for example, to help a
friend in need; but he could also be thought to have
duties towards software producers, for example, to
ensure the maintenance of a proper environment for
software production.
Virtue ethics. According to virtue ethics, when
faced with an ethical dilemma we need first to ask
what kind of people we are (or would like to be) in
order to select from possible courses of action
(Pence, 1993; Macintyre, 1987; Crisp and Slote,
1997). Virtue theory itself does not equip us with
good virtues, but leaves the course of action to be
chosen to the moral agent him/herself. In our
example, the student could deliberate with himself
about what kind of a human being, or in this
instance, the kind of friend or citizen he is or would
like to be. For example, he might decide that as a
friend he would like to be helpful but as a citizen he
would like to foster a good environment for software
production.
Rawls theory of justice: “veil of ignorance”. The
key element in Rawls’ (1971) theory of justice is the
so-called veil of ignorance. The veil of ignorance
seeks to guarantee fair and just treatment for all
members of society. The veil of ignorance is applied
in an imaginary negotiation, with the purpose of
achieving justice or equality in society. Ideally in
negotiations behind the veil of ignorance each
participant is unaware of who s/he is, of his/her
gender, preferences, profession, financial situation,
status, and interests in society. According to Rawls,
the process of deciding an issue behind the veil of
ignorance is fair and just, because we are then forced
to choose impartially (as we do not know who we
are in society). However, under the veil, participants
know certain facts, such as inequalities. When
deciding on the principles to be followed under the
veil, each participant also has the right to veto an
agreement. Under the veil the least advantaged
parties (e.g., disabled people) are protected, because
no one knows who s/he will be after the raising of
the veil. Rawls’ (1971) veil of ignorance is also
aimed at solving moral conflicts (Collins and Miller,
1992). When solving a moral conflict, one may
arrange an imaginary negotiation behind the veil,
during which the participants try to achieve a
solution to the conflict.
In our case, the student could imagine a
negotiation, in which he, his friend, and a
representative of the software producer are present.
They (the student, his friend and the representative
of the software producer) do not know their identity
in real life (hence the term ‘veil of ignorance’). They
might equally be software producers as students.
Given this situation, they try to achieve a consensus
relating to the production and delivery of software.
A possible resolution, which might be accepted by
all parties, would be as follows: every one should be
properly compensated for their work and for people
on low incomes (e.g., students), software producers
should offer discounted licensing fees.
ICEIS 2004 - HUMAN-COMPUTER INTERACTION
180