you, we can say that person has the power of
control” (Nockleby, 2002). In our approach these
types of privacy are variations of privacy as the right
to be alone. We can notice that active privacy is a
‘right-base’ privacy while passive privacy is a ‘duty-
based’ privacy. In the classical rights theory,
positive rights are rights to “caring actions” from
other people while negative rights, by contrast, are
rights of non-interference. Negative rights are
classified as (a) Active rights (or liberty rights)
which are rights to do as one chooses (b) Passive
rights which involve the right to let alone. We claim
that the “to-be-let-alone” apparatus encompasses
what is called negative rights. Also, passive privacy
appears in different fashions. According to O’Brien
(O’Brien, 1979) privacy “may be understood as
fundamentally denoting an existential condition of
limited access to an individual’s life experiences and
engagements.” This statement has passivity
ingredient. Similar feature of passivity appears when
Justice Douglas wrote in 1967, “Those who wrote
the Bill of Rights believed that every individual
needs both to communicate with others and to keep
his affairs to himself. That dual aspect of privacy
means that the individual should have the freedom to
select for himself the time and circumstances when
he will share his secrets" (Smith, 2000).
It can be noted that many dictionaries mention
two senses of privacy: a type of freedom (from
intrusion) and a quality of a state (e.g., seclusion).
Our active and passive features of privacy offer
clearer classification of the notion. Freedom also has
two senses: active (unrestricted activity) and passive
(the absence of outside pressure or constraint).
It is interesting here to explore the notion of
“passive freedom” further. “Privacy is not identical
with control over access to oneself, because not all
privacy is chosen. Some privacy is accidental,
compulsory, or even involuntary” (O’Brien, 1979).
This passive freedom is usually qualified with the
term “from” such as freedom “from intrusion”,
“from unwarranted publicity”, “from using one's
name or likeness”, “from unnecessary attacks on
reputation”, etc. Sometimes it is stated in terms of
“free of” as in the right to be free of door-to-door
solicitors. Passivity here denotes being in a state in
which the individual does not have immediate
control over the resultant freedom as this freedom
depends on how others respect their duties. When
“to” is used with this passive freedom it refers to
“others” doing some activities that affect the privacy
of the individual. For example, others attempt “to
control the moral content of a person's thought”, “to
search or seizure private...”, etc. Clearly, in these
situation the individual is a passive agent. Also “to”
may be used in conjunction with a very general
sense of freedom that includes active and passive
freedom; for example, freedom “to enjoy a private
life” means freedom “from” bodily restraint, and
freedom “to” engage in any of the common
occupations of life, etc.
The interpretation of the “right to be let alone” as
“freedom from” or passive privacy means “the right
to not-being an object to (others’) activities’. Hence,
“to be let alone” is sometimes rephrased as to be
“left” alone where ‘left’ means untouched or hands
off. This sense of freedom is in line with the Kantian
notion of human beings as ends in themselves and
the need to define and pursue one's own values free
from the impingement of others. Also, Justice Louis
Brandeis in his much quoted statement “[T]he right
to be let alone is the most comprehensive of rights
and the right most valued by civilized men” may
refer largely to this type of freedom. This freedom
has also a touch of the existentialist’s view of man
as "a free being" that must be left alone to realize
his/her true nature. Passive freedom has no control
element; just one wants others not paying attention
since he/she does not do any activities that attract
attention. Passivity here refers to no extra-activity
besides normal activities. This freedom means to be
‘free to enjoy good life’ while ‘melting in the crowd’
and having immunity from the focused attention of
others including the State. The assumption here is
that if one doesn’t attract the attention of others then
others will not subject him/her to their activities.
There is no sense in “relinquishing privacy” in this
case because “relinquishing” contradicts passivity.
This type of freedom can be classified under what is
called “inalienable rights” that cannot be
surrendered. Brandeis and Warren used ‘natural law’
as a base for the right to privacy in this sense. It is a
special type of the general Freedom advocated by
many great men as the right that “consists in a
Freedom from any superior Power on Earth, and not
being under the Will or legislative Authority of Man,
and having only the Law of Nature (or in other
Words, of its MAKER) for his Rule” (Williams,
1744).
This passive freedom in private affairs is the one
described as valuable to maintain intimacy. Love,
friendship and trust are possible not in the
controlling mode of one’s affairs (free in doing
whatever one wants) but in the context of ‘living
one’s affairs’ where one expects no others’ attention
(free from subjection by others). It does not embed
domination over others. An intimate relationship
such as love grows naturally in the middle of the
crowd, spontaneously, uncontrollable (by ones
involved), and free. The lovers feel uninhibited
(hiding it/ announcing it) because others are
basically and non-negatively don’t care. Freedom
here is not ‘control’ because the lovers are passive –
they are not playing the control game: allowing or
ICEIS 2005 - INFORMATION SYSTEMS ANALYSIS AND SPECIFICATION
104