HasEnd: EndofMay
HasBeginning: BeginningofMay
3.4 Vague Time Intervals
Many domains (geology, history and geography) are
faced with the problem of having vague temporal
information. In these cases, instants have no precise
position and intervals have no precise beginning and
end. This may also refer to the granularity issue. A
crisp time interval may become vague when the
working context shifts from a coarser granularity to
a finer granularity. In GTO, the class of vague
convex regions is used for representing the vague
temporal information (Figure 2). Rough set (Pawlak
1982) and fuzzy set (Zadeh 1965; Pawlak 1982) are
currently the most frequently used theories in
dealing with vague temporal information. The main
difference between them is that fuzzy set has
gradually-changing confidence (between 0 and 1)
according to a function while rough set only has
triplex value (0, 1 or uncertain). In GTO rough set
regions have properties such as upper approximation,
lower approximation whilst fuzzy set regions have
properties such as core, support and kernel (Figure
2).
3.5 Linking Time and Individuals
Because temporal information only makes sense
when it is associated with atemporal individuals (e.g.
process, event or object), it is important to formalise
the links between time and individuals. Currently,
most fundamental ontologies accept the distinction
between endurant individuals and perdurant
individuals, which are called differently in
fundamental ontologies (Table 1). The difference
between endurants and perdurants derives from their
relations to time (Bittner et al. 2004). Endurants are
wholly present at any time they are present, for
example, a book, a lake. Perdurants are wholly
present at any time they are present but extend in
time by accumulating different time parts (Navigli et
al. 2003), for example, a war, a storm. All
individuals are located in time regions that are
similar to spatial locations in the physical space. In
most fundamental ontologies, there is a basic link
between time and individuals (Table 1). For example,
GFO and SUMO only defines the most general link
between time and individual. DOLCE views time as
a subtype of quality like colour, size or weight. This
representation is unintuitive and also problematic
because other qualities also (e.g. colour, size) exist in
time. In our view, both endurants and perdurants are
located in time regions. More specifically, endurants
are wholly present during intervals or present at
instants, whilst perdurants persist during intervals
(e.g. state, process) or happen at instants (e.g. event,
changes). All other specific links between time and
individuals can be developed from them.
Table 1: Distinction of Individuals in Fundamental
Ontologies.
Fundamental
Ontology
Perduring
Individual
Enduring
Individual
Links between Time and
Individuals
DOLCE Perdurant Endurant has-quality (individuals,
temporal-quality)
q-location (temporal-quality,
temporal region)
GFO Process Persential project-to (entities, temporal
region)
BFO Occurrent Continuant N/A
SUMO Process Object when (Individuals, Time)
4 CONCLUSIONS AND FUTURE
WORK
This paper sketched GTO, which is a framework of
an upper ontology for temporal concepts. We
integrated merits from existing temporal ontologies
but also proposed our view on some specific issues
(general taxonomy, time description and non-convex
region, granularity and vague time intervals).
Compared with existing temporal ontologies, GTO
aims to provid a more complete framework of time
abstraction that can be applied into in a broad range
of domains. It not only can annotate everyday
temporal terms on the Web, but can also be further
extended for temporal concepts in particular domains
such as history, geography and archeology. Thus,
GTO may be useful in a knowledge infrastructure
which stores temporal information in different time
systems, for example, cooperating with the SKI
ontology (Brodaric et al. 2008). GTO emphasizes on
the representation of more complete temporal
semantics but ignores some reasoning problems such
as granularity and topological relations.
In the next step, more work is needed for improving
the GTO ontology, including defining temporal
relations, representing more complex non-convex
regions and coupling GTO with fundamental
ontologies. Additionally, some use cases will be
developed to assess the utility of GTO in negotiating
different temporal semantics. Its applications in
knowledge management will be further studied,
which may lay a foundation for a temporally robust
knowledge infrastructure.
TOWARDS A GENERAL TEMPORAL ONTOLOGY FOR KNOWLEDGE INTEGRATION
279