time intervals, and mereologies and orderings. In this
way, existing temporal ontologies found in COLORE
can be used to analyze the interpretations between the
DOLCE and PSL. Here we briefly outline the time
point and time interval ontologies used. We then ex-
amine a set of time ontologies from COLORE which
merge the time point ontologies with the time interval
ontologies.
4.1 The Time Points Hierarchy
Within this hierarchy are ontologies that describe time
in terms of time points and that introduce a par-
tial ordering on the set of time points using the bi-
nary relation be f ore(x, y). We are particularly inter-
ested in two of these ontologies, based on the roles
they play as modules of other ontologies. The lin-
ear point theory, T
linear point
4
, derived from axioms
found in (Hayes, 1996), is a simple ontology whose
axioms state that time points infinitely extend a time-
line in both forward and backward directions. The
linear time points with endpoints at infinity theory,
T
l p in f inite end
5
, derived from axioms found in (Hayes,
1996), also represents a linear ordering on time points
that infinitely extends in both forward and backward
directions, but it contains axioms that enforce the ex-
istence of endpoints at infinity in both directions.
4.2 The Periods Hierarchy
The axioms for the periods hierarchy, H
periods
, were
proposed in (van Benthem, 1991), and additional in-
formation about other ontologies in this hierarchy can
be found in (Gr
¨
uninger et al., 2012). We are in-
terested in the in the weakest theory of this hier-
archy, T
periods
, since it is used by T
end points
, which
is described in Section 4.3. The Minimal Theory
of Periods, T
periods
, constitutes the minimal set of
conditions that must be met by any period struc-
ture (van Benthem, 1991). It contains two relations,
precedence(x, y) and inclusion(x, y), and two conser-
vative definitions, glb(x, y, z) and overlaps(x, y), as its
non-logical lexicon. Every element in the domain is
considered a time interval, and there are transitivity
and irreflexivity axioms for the precedence(x, y) re-
lation, making it a strict partial order; similarly, the
transitivity, reflexivity, and anti-symmetry axioms for
the inclusion(x, y) relation make it a partial order. As
well, the axiom, glb(x, y, z), guarantees the existence
of greatest lower bounds between overlapping inter-
vals defined by overlaps(x, y).
4
http://colore.oor.net/timepoints/linear point.clif
5
http://colore.oor.net/timepoints/lp infinite end.clif
An interesting property in these ontologies is the
convexity of time intervals. Intuitively, convex inter-
vals are those which have no gaps (Ladkin, 1986)
6
.
The convexity of time intervals requires an ordering
over time intervals and a mereology, and hence it
can be defined by ontologies in the H
periods
hierar-
chy. However, convexity is not definable in DOLCE
since it lacks an ordering on time intervals.
4.3 The Combined Time Hierarchy
Given that we want to merge ontologies from the
time points hierarchy with ontologies from the pe-
riods hierarchy, we need to consider ontologies that
include both time points and time intervals as primi-
tives, and define a set of functions and relations spec-
ifying the interactions between them. These time on-
tologies
7
are derived from the theories presented in
(Hayes, 1996), and have been modified and verified in
(Gruninger and Ong, 2011). Depending on the rela-
tions and functions used, these theories can represent
time in very different ways. For example, the theory
of endpoints, T
end points
, defines time points only as the
boundary of time intervals, where every interval is as-
sociated with exactly two time points: the begin of
and end of the interval. In contrast, the theory of time
point continuum, T
point continuum
, defines intervals by
the set of adjacent time points in which they are con-
tained; another theory, T
vector continuum
introduces the
concept of directionality by allowing ‘backward in-
tervals’ where the end of point is before the begin of
point in the timeline.
The theory of endpoints, T
end points
8
, combines the
language of intervals and points by defining the begi-
nof, endof, and between functions to relate time inter-
vals to time points and vice-versa. In this hierarchy,
this theory imports axioms from T
linear point
that de-
fine a binary be f ore(x, y) relation between time points
as transitive and irreflexive, and asserts that all time
points are linearly ordered and infinite in both direc-
tions. As well, this theory includes axioms that define
the meets at(i, x, j) relation as one between two inter-
vals and the point at which they meet along, restrict
begino f (i) to always come before the endo f (i) func-
tion, and states that intervals are between two points
if they are properly ordered.
The vector continuum theory, T
vector continuum
9
, in-
6
Additional information about the various relations
found in convex and non-convex intervals can be found in
(Ladkin, 1986).
7
http://colore.oor.net/combined time/
8
http://colore.oor.net/combined time/endpoints.clif
9
http://colore.oor.net/combined time/
vector continuum.clif
MergingtheDOLCEandPSLUpperOntologies
21