Intuitionistic De Morgan Verification and Falsification Logics
Norihiro Kamide
Department of Information and Electronic Engineering, Faculty of Science and Engineering,
Teikyo University, Utsunomiya, Tochigi, Japan
Keywords:
Paraconsistent Logic, De Morgan Laws, Sequent Calculus, Cut-elimination Theorem, Embedding Theorem.
Abstract:
In this paper, two new logics called intuitionistic De Morgan verification logic DV and intuitionistic De Mor-
gan falsification logic DF are introduced as a Gentzen-type sequent calculus. The logics DV and DF have De
Morgan-like laws with respect to implication and co-implication. These laws are analogous to the well-known
De Morgan laws with respect to conjunction and disjunction. On the one hand, DV can appropriately repre-
sent verification (or justification) of incomplete information, on the other hand DF can appropriately represent
falsification (or refutation) of incomplete information. Some theorems for embedding DV into DF and vice
versa are shown. The cut-elimination theorems for DV and DF are proved, and DV and DF are also shown to
be paraconsistent and decidable.
1 INTRODUCTION
Intuitionistic logic is well-known to be useful for
many computer science applications. For example,
it is useful for representing and realizing proof-as-
programs (Curry-Howard) paradigm, functional pro-
graming, logic programming, typed λ-calculus and
program extraction. A reason for the usefulness of
the intuitionistic logic is that it can appropriately rep-
resent verification of incomplete information. Vari-
ous extensions and modifications of the intuitionis-
tic logic, such as dual-intuitionistic logic (Czermak,
1977; Goodman, 1981; Urbas, 1996) and Nelson’s
paraconsistent four-valued logic (Almukdad and Nel-
son, 1984; Nelson, 1949), have been proposed for ap-
propriately representing verification, falsification and
inconsistency (or paraconsistency) of incomplete in-
formation.
In this paper, two new logics called intuitionis-
tic De Morgan verification logic DV and intuitionis-
tic De Morgan falsification logic DF are introduced
as a Gentzen-type sequent calculus. The logics DV
and DF have the following De Morgan-like laws
with respect to the implication connective and the
co-implication (subtraction, exclusion or explication)
connective :
1. (αβ) α←∼β,
2. (αβ) α→∼β.
These laws are analogous to the following well-
known De Morgan laws with respect to the conjunc-
tion connective and the disjunction connective :
1. (α β) α β,
2. (α β) α β.
The following De Morgan-like laws, which are re-
semble to the above De Morgan-like laws, were origi-
nally introduced and studied in (Kamide and Wans-
ing, 2010) for formalizing a duality principle for a
classical paraconsistent logic called symmetric para-
consistent logic.
1. (αβ) β←∼α,
2. (αβ) β→∼α.
The De Morgan-like laws in DV and DF are required
for showing a duality principle between DV and DF.
The duality principle does not hold for the logics
which are obtained from DV and DF by replacing
the De Morgan-like laws with the other De Morgan-
like laws introduced in (Kamide and Wansing, 2010),
although the cut-elimination theorem holds for these
modified logics.
DV is regarded as a variant of Nelson’s paracon-
sistent four-valued logic N4 (Almukdad and Nelson,
1984; Nelson, 1949; Wansing, 1993; Kamide and
Wansing, 2012; Kamide and Wansing, 2015), and DF
is regarded as the dual version of DV in the sense
that some theorems for embedding DV into DF and
vice versa hold. These embedding theorems, which
represent a duality principle between DV and DF,
are regarded as a characteristic property of DV and
DF, since similar embedding theorems do not hold
Kamide, N.
Intuitionistic De Morgan Verification and Falsification Logics.
DOI: 10.5220/0005629902330240
In Proceedings of the 8th International Conference on Agents and Artificial Intelligence (ICAART 2016) - Volume 2, pages 233-240
ISBN: 978-989-758-172-4
Copyright
c
2016 by SCITEPRESS – Science and Technology Publications, Lda. All rights reserved
233
for N4 and its straightforward dual-like counterpart.
Such dual logics like DF were originally studied as
the dual-intuitionistic logics (Czermak, 1977; Good-
man, 1981; Urbas, 1996), which have a Gentzen-type
sequent calculus in which sequents have the restric-
tion that the antecedent contains at most one formula.
DV and DF are, indeed, extensions of the positive
intuitionistic logic and the positive dual-intuitionistic
logic, respectively. Moreover, DV is regarded as a
modified intuitionistic version of the symmetric para-
consistent logic (Kamide and Wansing, 2010).
Since DV and DF do not have the law α α
of excluded middle, these logics are appropriate for
handling incomplete information. Moreover, since
DV and DF do not have the law (α α)β of ex-
plosion, these logics are regarded as paraconsistent
logics (Priest, 2002). Since the base-logics of DV
and DF, i.e., the positive intuitionistic logic and the
positive dual-intuitionistic logic, are known to be ap-
propriate for representing “verification (or justifica-
tion)” and “falsification (or refutation)”, respectively
(Shramko, 2005), DV and DF are regarded also as
suitable for representing verification and falsification,
respectively. Thus, on the one hand, DV is suitable
for representing verification of incomplete informa-
tion, on the other hand DF is suitable for representing
falsification of incomplete information.
The contents of this paper are then summarized
as follows. In Section 2, the logic DV is introduced
as a Gentzen-type sequent calculus, and some theo-
rems for embedding DV and its negation-free frag-
ment IC are proved. By using these embedding the-
orems, the cut-elimination theorem for DV is shown,
and DV is also shown to be paraconsistent and de-
cidable. In Section 3, the logic DF is introduced as
a Gentzen-type sequent calculus, and some theorems
for embedding DF and its negation-free fragment DC
are shown. By using these embedding theorems, the
cut-elimination theorem for DF is obtained, and DF is
shown to be paraconsistent and decidable. In Section
4, some theorems for embedding DV into DF and vice
versa, which represent a duality principle for them,
are shown. In Section 5, this paper is concluded.
2 INTUITIONISTIC DE MORGAN
VERIFICATION LOGIC
The language of intuitionistic De Morgan verifica-
tion logic consists of logical connectives
t
(con-
junction),
t
(disjunction),
t
(implication),
t
(co-
implication) and
t
(paraconsistent negation). Lower
case letters p,q,... are used for propositional vari-
ables, lower case Greek letters α, β, ... are used for
formulas, and Greek capital letters Γ, , ... are used
for finite (possibly empty) multisets of formulas.
These letters are also used for other logics discussed
in this paper. A positive sequent is an expression of
the form Γ γ where γ denotes a single formula or
the empty sequence. A negative sequent will also be
defined.
An expression L ` S is used to denote the fact that
a (positive/negative) sequent S is provable in a sequent
calculus L. An expression of the form α β is used
to represent both α β and β α. A rule R of infer-
ence is said to be admissible in a sequent calculus L if
the following condition is satisfied: for any instance
S
1
··· S
n
S
of R, if L ` S
i
for all i, then L ` S. Since all logics dis-
cussed in this paper are formulated as sequent calculi,
we will frequently identify a sequent calculus with the
logic determined by it.
A Gentzen-type sequent calculus DV for intuition-
istic De Morgan verification logic is defined as fol-
lows based on positive sequents.
Definition 2.1 (DV). The initial sequents of DV are
of the following form, for any propositional variable
p:
p p
t
p
t
p.
The structural rules of DV are of the form:
Γ α α,Σ γ
Γ,Σ γ
(t-cut)
α,α,Γ γ
α,Γ γ
(t-co-l)
Γ γ
α,Γ γ
(t-we-l)
Γ
Γ α
(t-we-r).
The positive logical inference rules of DV are of
the form:
α,Γ γ
α
t
β,Γ γ
(
t
l1)
β,Γ γ
α
t
β,Γ γ
(
t
l2)
Γ α Γ β
Γ α
t
β
(
t
r)
α,Γ γ β,Γ γ
α
t
β,Γ γ
(
t
l)
Γ α
Γ α
t
β
(
t
r1)
Γ β
Γ α
t
β
(
t
r2)
Γ α β, γ
α
t
β,Γ, γ
(
t
l)
α,Γ β
Γ α
t
β
(
t
r)
β,Γ γ
α
t
β,Γ γ
(
t
l1)
Γ α
α
t
β,Γ
(
t
l2)
α,Γ β
Γ, α
t
β
(
t
r).
The negative logical inference rules of DV are of
the form:
α,Γ γ
t
t
α,Γ γ
(
t
l)
Γ α
Γ
t
t
α
(
t
r)
ICAART 2016 - 8th International Conference on Agents and Artificial Intelligence
234
t
α,Γ γ
t
β,Γ γ
t
(α
t
β),Γ γ
(
t
t
l)
Γ
t
α
Γ
t
(α
t
β)
(
t
t
r1)
Γ
t
β
Γ
t
(α
t
β)
(
t
t
r2)
t
α,Γ γ
t
(α
t
β),Γ γ
(
t
t
l1)
t
β,Γ γ
t
(α
t
β),Γ γ
(
t
t
l2)
Γ
t
α Γ
t
β
Γ
t
(α
t
β)
(
t
t
r)
t
β,Γ γ
t
(α
t
β),Γ γ
(
t
t
l1)
Γ
t
α
t
(α
t
β),Γ
(
t
t
l2)
t
α,Γ
t
β
Γ,
t
(α
t
β)
(
t
t
r)
Γ
t
α
t
β, γ
t
(α
t
β),Γ, γ
(
t
t
l)
t
α,Γ
t
β
Γ
t
(α
t
β)
(
t
t
r).
Some remarks are given as follows.
1. The sequents of the form α α for any formula
α are provable in DV. This fact can be shown by
induction on α.
2. A sequent calculus for Nelson’s paraconsistent
four-valued logic N4 (Almukdad and Nelson,
1984; Nelson, 1949) is obtained from the
t
-
free fragment of DV by replacing {(
t
t
l1),
(
t
t
l2), (
t
t
r)} with the negative inference
rules of the form:
α,Γ γ
t
(α
t
β),Γ γ
(n
t
t
l1)
t
β,Γ γ
t
(α
t
β),Γ γ
(n
t
t
l2)
Γ α Γ
t
β
Γ
t
(α
t
β)
(n
t
t
r)
which correspond to the axiom scheme:
t
(α
t
β) (α
t
t
β).
Proposition 2.2. The following sequents are provable
in DV: for any formulas α and β,
1.
t
t
α α,
2.
t
(α
t
β) (
t
α
t
t
β),
3.
t
(α
t
β) (
t
α
t
t
β),
4.
t
(α
t
β) (
t
α
t
t
β),
5.
t
(α
t
β) (
t
α
t
t
β).
Proof. We show only the following case. (4):
.
.
.
.
t
α
t
α
t
(α
t
β),
t
α
(
t
t
l2)
.
.
.
.
t
β
t
β
t
(α
t
β)
t
β
(
t
t
l1)
t
(α
t
β),
t
(α
t
β)
t
α
t
t
β
(
t
r)
t
(α
t
β)
t
α
t
t
β
(t-co-r)
.
.
.
.
t
α
t
α
t
α
t
t
β,
t
α
(
t
l2)
.
.
.
.
t
β
t
β
t
α
t
t
β
t
β
(
t
l1)
t
α
t
t
β,
t
α
t
t
β
t
(α
t
β)
(
t
t
r)
t
α
t
t
β
t
(α
t
β)
(t-co-r).
Definition 2.3 (IC). A sequent calculus IC for posi-
tive intuitionistic logic with co-implication is defined
as the
t
-free fragment of DV, i.e., it is obtained
from DV by deleting the negative initial sequents
t
p
t
p and the negative logical inference rules
concerning
t
.
The following result is known (Urbas, 1996).
Proposition 2.4 (Cut-elimination and decidability for
IC). We have:
1. The rule (t-cut) is admissible in cut-free IC.
2. IC is decidable.
Next, we introduce a translation of DV into IC,
and by using this translation, we show some theorems
for embedding DV into IC. A similar translation has
been used by Gurevich (Gurevich, 1977), Rautenberg
(Rautenberg, 1979) and Vorob’ev (Vorob’ev, 1952)
to embed Nelson’s constructive logic (Almukdad and
Nelson, 1984; Nelson, 1949) into intuitionistic logic.
Definition 2.5. We fix a set Φ of propositional vari-
ables and define the set Φ
0
:= {p
0
| p Φ} of proposi-
tional variables. The language L
DV
of DV is defined
using Φ,
t
,
t
,
t
,
t
and
t
. The language L
IC
of
IC is obtained from L
DV
by adding Φ
0
and deleting
t
.
A mapping f from L
DV
to L
IC
is defined induc-
tively by:
1. for any p Φ, f (p) := p and f (
t
p) := p
0
Φ
0
,
2. f (α β) := f (α) f (β) where
{∧
t
,
t
,
t
,
t
},
3. f (
t
t
α) := f (α),
4. f (
t
(α
t
β)) := f (
t
α)
t
f (
t
β),
5. f (
t
(α
t
β)) := f (
t
α)
t
f (
t
β),
6. f (
t
(α
t
β)) := f (
t
α)
t
f (
t
β),
7. f (
t
(α
t
β)) := f (
t
α)
t
f (
t
β).
Intuitionistic De Morgan Verification and Falsification Logics
235
An expression f (Γ) denotes the result of replac-
ing every occurrence of a formula α in Γ by an oc-
currence of f (α). The same notation is used for other
mappings discussed in this paper.
We then obtain a weak theorem for syntactically
embedding DV into IC.
Theorem 2.6 (Weak embedding from DV into IC).
Let Γ be a set of formulas in L
DV
, γ be a formula in
L
DV
or the empty sequence, and f be the mapping
defined in Definition 2.5.
1. If DV ` Γ γ, then IC ` f (Γ) f (γ).
2. If IC (t-cut) ` f (Γ) f (γ), then DV (t-cut)
` Γ γ.
Proof. (1): By induction on the proofs P of Γ γ
in DV. We distinguish the cases according to the last
inference of P, and show some cases.
Case (
t
p
t
p): The last inference of P is of
the form:
t
p
t
p for any p Φ. In this case,
we obtain IC ` f (
t
p) f (
t
p), i.e., IC ` p
0
p
0
(p
0
Φ
0
), by the definition of f .
Case (
t
t
r): The last inference of P is of the
form:
t
α,Γ
t
β
Γ,
t
(α
t
β)
(
t
t
r).
By induction hypothesis, we have IC `
f (
t
α), f (Γ) and IC ` f () f (
t
β). Then, we
obtain the required fact:
.
.
.
.
f (
t
α), f (Γ)
.
.
.
.
f () f (
t
β)
f (Γ), f () f (
t
α)
t
f (
t
β)
(
t
r)
as f (
t
α)
t
f (
t
β) = f (
t
(α
t
β)).
Case (
t
t
l1): The last inference of P is of the
form:
t
β,Γ γ
t
(α
t
β),Γ γ
(
t
t
l1).
By induction hypothesis, we have IC `
f (
t
β), f (Γ) f (γ). Then, we obtain the re-
quired fact:
.
.
.
.
f (
t
β), f (Γ) f (γ)
f (
t
α)
t
f (
t
β), f (Γ) f (γ)
(
t
l1)
as f (
t
α)
t
f (
t
β) = f (
t
(α
t
β)).
Case (
t
t
l2): The last inference of P is of the
form:
Γ
t
α
t
(α
t
β),Γ
(
t
t
l2).
By induction hypothesis, we have IC `
f (Γ) f (
t
α). Then, we obtain the required
fact:
.
.
.
.
f (Γ) f (
t
α)
f (
t
α)
t
f (
t
β), f (Γ)
(
t
l2)
as f (
t
α)
t
f (
t
β) = f (
t
(α
t
β)).
(2): By induction on the proofs Q of f (Γ) f (γ)
in IC (t-cut). We distinguish the cases according to
the last inference of Q, and show only the following
case.
Case (
t
l): The last inference of Q is (
t
l).
Subcase (1): The last inference of Q is of the form:
f (Γ) f (α) f (β), f () f (γ)
f (α
t
β), f (Γ), f () f (γ)
(
t
l)
where f (α
t
β) coincides with f (α)
t
f (β) by the
definition of f . By induction hypothesis, we have DV
(t-cut) ` Γ α and DV (t-cut) ` β, γ. We
thus obtain the required fact:
.
.
.
.
Γ α
.
.
.
.
β, γ
α
t
β,Γ, γ
(
t
l).
Subcase (2): The last inference of Q is of the form:
f (Γ) f (
t
α) f (
t
β), f () f (γ)
f (
t
(α
t
β)), f (Γ), f () f (γ)
(
t
l)
as f (
t
(α
t
β)) = f (
t
α)
t
f (
t
β). By induction
hypothesis, we have DV (t-cut) ` Γ
t
α and DV
(t-cut) `
t
β, γ. We thus obtain the required
fact:
.
.
.
.
Γ
t
α
.
.
.
.
t
β, γ
t
(α
t
β),Γ, γ
(
t
t
l).
Using Theorem 2.6 and the cut-elimination theo-
rem for IC, we obtain the following cut-elimination
theorem for DV.
Theorem 2.7 (Cut-elimination for DV). The rule (t-
cut) is admissible in cut-free DV.
Proof. Suppose DV ` Γ γ. Then, we have IC
` f (Γ) f (γ) by Theorem 2.6 (1), and hence IC
(t-cut) ` f (Γ) f (γ) by the cut-elimination theorem
for IC. By Theorem 2.6 (2), we obtain DV (t-cut)
` Γ γ.
Using Theorem 2.6 and the cut-elimination theo-
rem for IC, we obtain the following strong theorem
for syntactically embedding DV into IC.
ICAART 2016 - 8th International Conference on Agents and Artificial Intelligence
236
Theorem 2.8 (Strong embedding from DV into IC).
Let Γ be a set of formulas in L
DV
, γ be a formula in
L
DV
or the empty sequence, and f be the mapping
defined in Definition 2.5.
1. DV ` Γ γ iff IC ` f (Γ) f (γ).
2. DV (t-cut) ` Γ γ iff IC (t-cut) `
f (Γ) f (γ).
Proof. (1): (=): By Theorem 2.6 (1). (=):
Suppose IC ` f (Γ) f (γ). Then we have IC (t-
cut) ` f (Γ) f (γ) by the cut-elimination theorem
for IC. We thus obtain DV (t-cut) ` Γ γ by The-
orem 2.6 (2). Therefore we have DV ` Γ γ.
(2): (=): Suppose DV (t-cut) ` Γ γ.
Then we have DV ` Γ γ. We then obtain IC
` f (Γ) f (γ) by Theorem 2.6 (1). Therefore
we obtain IC (t-cut) ` f (Γ) f (γ) by the cut-
elimination theorem for IC. (=): By Theorem 2.6
(2).
Using Theorem 2.7, we show the paraconsistency
of DV with respect to
t
.
Definition 2.9. Let ] be a negation (-like) connective.
A sequent calculus L is called explosive with respect
to ] if for any formulas α and β, the sequent α,]α β
is provable in L. It is called paraconsistent with re-
spect to ] if it is not explosive with respect to ].
Theorem 2.10 (Paraconsistency for DV). DV is para-
consistent with respect to
t
.
Proof. Consider a sequent p,
t
p q where
p and q are distinct propositional variables. Then,
the unprovability of this sequent can be shown using
Theorem 2.7.
Using Theorem 2.8 and the decidability of IC, we
show the decidability of DV.
Theorem 2.11 (Decidability for DV). DV is decid-
able.
Proof. By decidability of IC, for each α, it is pos-
sible to decide if f (α) is provable in DV. Then, by
Theorem 2.8, IC is decidable.
3 INTUITIONISTIC DE MORGAN
FALSIFICATION LOGIC
The language of intuitionistic De Morgan falsi-
fication logic consists of logical connectives
f
(dual-conjunction),
f
(dual-disjunction),
f
(dual-
implication),
f
(dual-co-implication) and
f
(dual-
paraconsistent negation). A negative sequent is an ex-
pression of the form γ Γ where γ denotes a single
formula or the empty sequence.
A Gentzen-type sequent calculus DF for intuition-
istic De Morgan falsification logic is defined as fol-
lows based on negative sequents.
Definition 3.1 (DF). The initial sequents of DF are of
the following form, for any propositional variable p:
p p
f
p
f
p.
The structural rules of DF are of the form:
γ Γ,α α
γ Γ,
(f-cut)
γ Γ,α,α
γ Γ,α
(f-co-r)
γ Γ
γ Γ,α
(f-we-r)
Γ
α Γ
(f-we-l).
The positive logical inference rules of DF are of
the form:
α Γ
α
f
β Γ
(
f
l1)
β Γ
α
f
β Γ
(
f
l2)
γ Γ,α γ Γ,β
γ Γ,α
f
β
(
f
r)
α Γ β Γ
α
f
β Γ
(
f
l)
γ Γ,α
γ Γ,α
f
β
(
f
r1)
γ Γ,β
γ Γ,α
f
β
(
f
r2)
Γ,α β
α
f
β Γ,
(
f
l)
γ Γ,β
γ Γ,α
f
β
(
f
r1)
α Γ
Γ,α
f
β
(
f
r2)
β Γ,α
α
f
β Γ
(
f
l)
α Γ γ ,β
γ Γ,,α
f
β
(
f
r).
The negative logical inference rules of DF are of
the form:
α Γ
f
f
α Γ
(
f
l)
γ Γ,α
γ Γ,
f
f
α
(
f
r)
f
α Γ
f
β Γ
f
(α
f
β) Γ
(
f
f
l)
γ Γ,
f
α
γ Γ,
f
(α
f
β)
(
f
f
r1)
γ Γ,
f
β
γ Γ,
f
(α
f
β)
(
f
f
r2)
f
α Γ
f
(α
f
β) Γ
(
f
f
l1)
f
β Γ
f
(α
f
β) Γ
(
f
f
l2)
γ Γ,
f
α γ Γ,
f
β
γ Γ,
f
(α
f
β)
(
f
f
r)
f
β Γ,
f
α
f
(α
f
β) Γ
(
f
f
l)
Intuitionistic De Morgan Verification and Falsification Logics
237
f
α Γ γ ,
f
β
γ Γ,,
f
(α
f
β)
(
f
f
r)
Γ,
f
α
f
β
f
(α
f
β) Γ,
(
f
f
l)
γ Γ,
f
β
γ Γ,
f
(α
f
β)
(
f
f
r1)
f
α Γ
Γ,
f
(α
f
β)
(
f
f
r2).
Some remarks are given as follows.
1. The sequents of the form α α for any formula
α are provable in DF. This fact can be shown by
induction on α.
2. The following sequents are provable in DF: for
any formulas α and β,
(a)
f
f
α α,
(b)
f
(α
f
β) (
f
α
f
f
β),
(c)
f
(α
f
β) (
f
α
f
f
β),
(d)
f
(α
f
β) (
f
α
f
f
β),
(e)
f
(α
f
β) (
f
α
f
f
β).
3. A sequent calculus for a dual-like version of N4
is obtained from the
f
-free fragment of DF by
replacing {(
f
f
l), (
f
f
r)} with the negative
inference rules of the form:
α Γ
f
(α
f
β) Γ
(dn
f
f
l1)
f
β Γ
f
(α
f
β) Γ
(dn
f
f
l2)
γ Γ,α γ Γ,
f
β
γ Γ,
f
(α
f
β)
(dn
f
f
r)
which correspond to the axiom scheme:
f
(α
f
β) (α
f
f
β).
Definition 3.2 (DC). A sequent calculus DC for posi-
tive dual-intuitionistic logic with co-implication is de-
fined as the
f
-free fragment of DF, i.e., it is ob-
tained from DF by deleting the negative initial se-
quents
f
p
f
p and the negative logical infer-
ence rules concerning
f
.
The following result is known (Urbas, 1996).
Proposition 3.3 (Cut-elimination and decidability for
DC). We have:
1. The rule (f-cut) is admissible in cut-free DC.
2. DC is decidable.
The following definition is similar to Definition
2.5.
Definition 3.4. We fix a set Φ of propositional vari-
ables and define the set Φ
0
:= {p
0
| p Φ} of propo-
sitional variables. The language L
DF
of DF is defined
using Φ,
f
,
f
,
f
,
f
and
f
. The language L
DC
of DC is obtained from L
DF
by adding Φ
0
and deleting
f
.
A mapping g from L
DF
to L
DC
is defined induc-
tively by:
1. for any p Φ, g(p) := p and g(
f
p) := p
0
Φ
0
,
2. g(α β) := g(α) g(β) where
{∧
f
,
f
,
f
,
f
},
3. g(
f
f
α) := g(α),
4. g(
f
(α
f
β)) := g(
f
α)
f
g(
f
β),
5. g(
f
(α
f
β)) := g(
f
α)
f
g(
f
β),
6. g(
f
(α
f
β)) := g(
f
α)
f
g(
f
β),
7. g(
f
(α
f
β)) := g(
f
α)
f
g(
f
β).
Theorem 3.5 (Weak embedding from DF into DC).
Let Γ be a set of formulas in L
DF
, γ be a formula in
L
DF
or the empty sequence, and f be the mapping
defined in Definition 3.4.
1. If DF ` γ Γ, then DC ` g(γ) g(Γ).
2. If DC (f-cut) ` g(γ) g(Γ), then DF (f-cut)
` γ Γ.
Proof. Similar to Theorem 2.6.
Theorem 3.6 (Cut-elimination for DF). The rule (f-
cut) is admissible in cut-free DF.
Proof. Similar to Theorem 2.7. By Theorem 3.5
and the cut-elimination theorem for DC.
Theorem 3.7 (Strong embedding from DF into CD).
Let Γ be a set of formulas in L
DF
, γ be a formula in
L
DF
or the empty sequence, and g be the mapping
defined in Definition 3.4.
1. DF ` γ Γ iff DC ` g(γ) g(G).
2. DF (f-cut) ` γ Γ iff DC (f-cut) `
g(γ) g(Γ).
Proof. Similar to Theorem 2.8. By Theorem 3.5
and the cut-elimination theorem for CD.
Theorem 3.8 (Paraconsistency for DF). DF is para-
consistent with respect to
f
.
Proof. By Theorem 3.6.
Theorem 3.9 (Decidability for DF). DF is decidable.
Proof. By Theorem 2.8 and the decidability of
CD.
ICAART 2016 - 8th International Conference on Agents and Artificial Intelligence
238
4 DUALITY
Next, we introduce a translation from DF into DV.
The idea of this translation comes from (Czermak,
1977; Urbas, 1996).
Definition 4.1. We fix a common set Φ of proposi-
tional variables. The language L
DF
of DF is defined
using Φ,
f
,
f
,
f
,
f
and
f
. The language L
DV
of DV is defined using Φ,
t
,
t
,
t
,
t
and
t
.
A mapping h from L
DF
to L
DV
is defined induc-
tively by:
1. h(p) := p for any p Φ,
2. h(α
f
β) := h(α)
t
h(β),
3. h(α
f
β) := h(α)
t
h(β),
4. h(α
f
β) := h(α)
t
h(β),
5. h(α
f
β) := h(α)
t
h(β),
6. h(
f
α) :=
t
h(α).
Theorem 4.2 (Strong embedding from DF into DV).
Let Γ be a set of formulas in L
DF
, γ be a formula in
L
DF
or the empty sequence, and h be the mapping
defined in Definition 4.1.
1. DF ` γ Γ iff DV ` h(Γ) h(γ).
2. DF (f-cut) ` γ Γ iff DV (t-cut) `
h(Γ) h(γ).
Proof. We show only (1) since (2) can be ob-
tained as a subproof of (1). We show only the direc-
tion (=) of (1) by induction on the proof P of γ Γ
in DF. We distinguish the cases according to the last
inference of P, and show some cases.
Case (
f
f
l): The last inference of P is of the
form:
f
β Γ,
f
α
f
(α
f
β) Γ
(
f
f
l).
By induction hypothesis, we have DV `
h(Γ),h(
f
α) h(
f
β) where h(
f
α) and h(
f
β)
respectively coincide with
t
h(α) and
t
h(β) by the
definition of h. Then, we obtain the required fact:
.
.
.
.
h(Γ),
t
h(α)
t
h(β)
h(Γ)
t
(h(α)
t
h(β))
(
t
t
r)
as
t
(h(α)
t
h(β)) = h(
f
(α
f
β)).
Case (
f
f
r): The last inference of P is of the
form:
f
α Γ γ ,
f
β
γ Γ,,
f
(α
f
β)
(
f
f
r).
By induction hypothesis, we have DV `
h(Γ) h(
f
α) and DV ` h(),h(
f
β) h(γ)
where h(
f
α) and h(
f
β) respectively coincide
with
t
h(α) and
t
h(β) by the definition of h. Then,
we obtain the required fact:
.
.
.
.
h(Γ)
t
h(α)
.
.
.
.
h(),
t
h(β) h(γ)
t
(h(α)
t
h(β)),h(Γ),h() h(γ)
(
t
t
l)
as
t
(h(α)
t
h(β)) = h(
f
(α
f
β)).
Case (
f
f
l): The last inference of P is of the
form:
Γ,
f
α
f
β
f
(α
f
β) Γ,
(
f
f
l).
By induction hypothesis, we have DV `
h(Γ),h(
f
α) and DV ` h() h(
f
β)
where h(
f
α) and h(
f
β) respectively coincide
with
t
h(α) and
t
h(β) by the definition of h. Then,
we obtain the required fact:
.
.
.
.
h(Γ),
t
h(α)
.
.
.
.
h()
t
h(β)
h(Γ),h()
t
(h(α)
t
h(β))
(
t
t
r)
as
t
(h(α)
t
h(β)) = h(
f
(α
f
β)).
Case (
f
f
r1): The last inference of P is of the
form:
γ Γ,
f
β
γ Γ,
f
(α
f
β)
(
f
f
r1).
By induction hypothesis, we have DV `
h(Γ),h(
f
β) h(γ) where h(
f
β) coincides
with
t
h(β) by the definition of h. Then, we obtain
the required fact:
.
.
.
.
h(Γ),
t
h(β) h(γ)
t
(h(α)
t
h(β)),h(Γ) h(γ)
(
t
t
l1)
as
t
(h(α)
t
h(β)) = h(
f
(α
f
β)).
Case (
f
f
r2): The last inference of P is of the
form:
f
α Γ
Γ,
f
(α
f
β)
(
f
f
r2).
By induction hypothesis, we have DV `
h(Γ) h(
f
α) where h(
f
α) coincides with
t
h(α) by the definition of h. Then, we obtain the
required fact:
.
.
.
.
h(Γ)
t
h(α)
t
(h(α)
t
h(β)),h(Γ)
(
t
t
l2)
as
t
(h(α)
t
h(β)) = h(
f
(α
f
β)).
We can introduce a translation from DV into DF
in a similar way.
Intuitionistic De Morgan Verification and Falsification Logics
239
Definition 4.3. Φ, L
DF
and L
DV
are the same as in
Definition 4.1.
A mapping k from L
DV
to L
DF
is defined induc-
tively by:
1. k(p) := p for any p Φ,
2. k(α
t
β) := k(α)
f
k(β),
3. k(α
t
β) := k(α)
f
k(β),
4. k(α
t
β) := k(α)
f
k(β),
5. k(α
t
β) := k(α)
f
k(β),
6. k(
t
α) :=
f
k(α).
Theorem 4.4 (Strong embedding from DV into DF).
Let Γ be a set of formulas in L
DV
, γ be a formula in
L
DV
or the empty sequence, and k be the mapping
defined in Definition 4.3.
1. DV ` Γ γ iff DF ` k(γ) k(Γ).
2. DV (t-cut) ` Γ γ iff DF (f-cut) `
k(γ) k(Γ).
Proof. Similar to Theorem 4.2.
Some remarks are given as follows.
1. The cut-elimination theorems for DV and DF can
be obtained using Theorems 4.2 and 4.4.
2. The following hold for DV and DF:
(a) DV ` hk(Γ) hk(γ) iff DV ` Γ γ,
(b) DF ` kh(γ) kh(Γ) iff DF ` γ Γ.
3. A similar theorem for embedding N4 into its dual-
like version displayed in Section 3 cannot be
shown. Thus, the duality principle for these logics
do not hold.
5 CONCLUSIONS
In this paper, the new logics DV and DF which have
the De Morgan-like laws with respect to the implica-
tion and co-implication connectives were introduced
as a Gentzen-type sequent calculus. DV and DF are
natural extensions of the positive intuitionistic logic
and the positive dual-intuitionistic logic, respectively.
Some theorems for embedding DV and DF into their
negation-free fragments were proved, and some theo-
rems for embedding DV into DF and vice versa were
shown. By using these embedding theorems, the cut-
elimination theorems for DV and DF were obtained,
and DV and DF were also shown to be paraconsistent
and decidable. Also, as remarked in Section 1, the
logics DV and DF are suitable for representing ver-
ification and falsification of incomplete information.
We thus believe that DV and DF are a promising ba-
sis for many computer science applications, as for the
intuitionistic and dual-intuitionistic logics.
ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS
We would like to thank anonymous referees for their
valuable comments. This work was supported by
JSPS KAKENHI Grant (C) 26330263 and by Grant-
in-Aid for Okawa Foundation for Information and
Telecommunications.
REFERENCES
Almukdad, A. and Nelson, D. (1984). Constructible falsity
and inexact predicates. Journal of Symbolic Logic,
49:231–233.
Czermak, J. (1977). A remark on gentzen’s calculus of se-
quents. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 18:471–
474.
Goodman, N. (1981). The logic of contradiction. Z. Math.
Logik Grundlagen Math., 27:119–126.
Gurevich, Y. (1977). Intuitionistic logic with strong nega-
tion. Studia Logica, 36:49–59.
Kamide, N. and Wansing, H. (2010). Symmetric and dual
paraconsistent logics. Logic and Logical Philosophy,
19 (1-2):7–30.
Kamide, N. and Wansing, H. (2012). Proof theory of nel-
son’s paraconsistent logic: A uniform perspective.
Theoretical Computer Science, 415:1–38.
Kamide, N. and Wansing, H. (2015). Proof theory of N4-
related paraconsistent logics, Studies in Logic 54.
College Publications.
Nelson, D. (1949). Constructible falsity. Journal of Sym-
bolic Logic, 14:16–26.
Priest, G. (2002). Paraconsistent logic, Handbook of Philo-
sophical Logic (Second Edition), Vol. 6, D. Gabbay
and F. Guenthner (eds.). Kluwer Academic Publish-
ers, Dordrecht, pp. 287-393.
Rautenberg, W. (1979). Klassische und nicht-klassische
Aussagenlogik. Vieweg, Braunschweig.
Shramko, Y. (2005). Dual intuitionistic logic and a variety
of negations: The logic of scientific research. Studia
Logica, 80 (2-3):347–367.
Urbas, I. (1996). Dual-intuitionistic logic. Notre Dame
Journal of Formal Logic, 37:440–451.
Vorob’ev, N. (1952). A constructive propositional calculus
with strong negation (in Russian). Doklady Akademii
Nauk SSR, 85:465–468.
Wansing, H. (1993). The logic of information structures.
In Lecture Notes in Computer Science, volume 681,
pages 1–163.
ICAART 2016 - 8th International Conference on Agents and Artificial Intelligence
240