The Dynamics of Narrow-minded Belief
Shoshin Nomura
1
, Norihiro Arai
2
and Satoshi Tojo
2
1
National Institute of Informatics, Japan
2
Japan Advanced Institute of Science and Technology, Japan
Keywords:
Dynamic Epistemic Logic, Public Announcement Logic, Logic of Passion, Narrow-minded Belief.
Abstract:
The purpose of this paper is to consider and formalize an important factor of human intelligence, belief affected
by passion, which we call narrow-minded belief. Based on Public Announcement Logic, we define our logic,
Logic Of Narrow-minded belief (LON), as that which includes such belief. Semantics for LON is provided
by the Kripke-style semantics, and a proof system for it is given by the Hilbert-style proof system. We then
provide a proof of the semantic completeness theorem for the proof system with the innermost strategy of
reducing a formula for LON. Using LON, we formally analyze the mental state of the hero of Shakespeare’s
tragedy Othello as an example of narrow-minded belief and its formalization.
1 INTRODUCTION
Love is blind, and hatred is also blind. To gener-
alize these phrases, we may say that passion causes
narrow-mindedness. It is not unusual that people can-
not emotionally stop believing what they do not want
to believe without any specific reason to believe so.
The hero of William Shakespeare’s play, Othello, is
involved in a pitiful but possible situation where he
wants to believe his wife’s chastity but he cannot since
he heard a bad rumor about her. It may be difficult to
answer whether or not he believes that his wife is a
betrayer of their marriage given that he has heard this
rumor. In this situation, Othello has at least two dif-
ferent types of belief and/or knowledge. One is pas-
sionate or narrow-minded belief, which he is willing
to believe or cannot stop believing emotionally. The
other is belief, which is more rational (less passionate)
or, without considering any philosophical discussions
regarding the relationship between knowledge and be-
lief, it may even be said, is knowledge whereby he
judges something based on information attained via
rational inferences. The latter type of knowledge or
belief is treated by a standard epistemic (or doxastic)
logic and the current researchers would like to intro-
duce the former belief, passionate belief or narrow-
minded belief.
In fact, the notion of passion has a philosophically
and psychologically profound meaning in terms of be-
lief, and it is highly possible that such emotional be-
lief plays a significant role in rationality. In A Treatise
of Human Nature, Hume famously (or even notori-
ously) wrote the following quotation.
[T]he principle, which opposes our passion,
cannot be the same with reason, and is only
called so in an improper sense. We speak not
strictly and philosophically when we talk of
the combat of passion and of reason. Reason
is, and ought only to be the slave of the pas-
sions [...]. (Hume, 1739, Book II, Sec. 3, Part
3).
Here, Hume says not only that passion has the same
significance as rationality, but also that reason is a
subordinate of passion. We introduce one more quo-
tation from modern literature, Damasio’s Descartes’
error, to support the importance of consideration on
the relationship between passion and rationality.
[T]here may be a connecting trail, in anatom-
ical and functional terms, from reason to feel-
ings to body. It is as if we are possessed by a
passion for reason [...]. Reason, from the prac-
tical to the theoretical, is probably constructed
on this inherent drive by a process which re-
sembles the mastering of a skill or craft. Re-
move the drive, and you will not acquire the
mastery. But having the drive does not auto-
matically make you a master. (Damasio, 1994,
Part III, Chap. 11)
By referring neurological evidence, Damasio argues
that feeling (or passion) and rationality are strongly
connected with other, and they cannot be separated
Nomura, S., Arai, N. and Tojo, S.
The Dynamics of Narrow-minded Belief.
DOI: 10.5220/0007394502470255
In Proceedings of the 11th International Conference on Agents and Artificial Intelligence (ICAART 2019), pages 247-255
ISBN: 978-989-758-350-6
Copyright
c
2019 by SCITEPRESS Science and Technology Publications, Lda. All rights reserved
247
as Descartes thought. The current researchers would
like to take a similar stance to that of Damasio, where
passion and rationality (in our term, narrow-minded
belief and knowledge) are related to one another in a
formal language of epistemic logic.
In this paper, we treat such a paradigm of agent
communication that each agent changes his/her belief,
after receiving messages from others, to strengthen/
weaken his/her tolerance. Towards this motivation,
we present a logic that adequately reflects human
minds which tends to be biased by certain kinds of
information.
The outline of the paper is as follows. In Section 2,
we introduce logic of narrow-minded belief (LON)
which is based on Public Announcement Logic by
Plaza (Plaza, 1989) and refers to the ideas of explicit
and implicit belief in dynamic epistemic awareness
logic by van Benthem & Vel
´
azquez-Quesada (van
Benthem and Vel
´
azquez-Quesada, 2010). Its seman-
tics are given by an expansion of the Kripke-style se-
mantics. In Section 3, we attempt to investigate and
formalize a person’s belief and emotion through fo-
cusing on a literary work, Othello since this is a story
of delicate transition of the hero’s narrow-minded be-
lief towards his wife. In Section 4, we introduce a
Hilbert-style proof system LON of LON, and some
proof theoretic properties. In Section 5, we give
a proof of the semantic completeness of our proof
system LON (Theorem 5.4) through the innermost
strategy for reducing a formula for LON into a for-
mula without announcement operators. In Section 6,
we introduce related epistemic/doxastic logics to the
present work.
2 LANGUAGE AND SEMANTICS
OF LON
2.1 Language
First of all, we address the syntax of LON. Let
Atom = {p,q,. ..} be a countable set of atomic propo-
sitions. Then, formula ϕ of the language L
(KN⊕!)
is
inductively defined as follows (p Atom):
ϕ ::= p | ¬ϕ | (ϕ ϕ) | Kϕ | Nϕ | [ϕ]ϕ | [ϕ]ϕ | [.!.ϕ]ϕ.
We define other Boolean connectives such as ϕ χ,
ϕ χ, ϕ χ and in a usual manner. We call oper-
ators [ϕ], [ϕ] and [.!.ϕ] announcement operators.
Besides,
b
K is defined by ¬K¬ and
b
N is defined by
¬N¬. Note that K and N can be considered as the
box operator 2 in modal logic, and
b
K and
b
N can be
considered as the diamond operator 3.
Kϕ reads ‘the agent knows that ϕ’,
Nϕ reads ‘the agent narrow-mindedly believes
that ϕ’,
[ϕ]χ reads ‘after obtaining information ϕ which
may strengthen the agent’s narrow-mindedness, χ
holds’,
[ϕ]χ reads ‘after obtaining information ϕ which
may weaken the agent’s narrow-mindedness, χ
holds,’ and
[.!.ϕ]χ reads ‘after obtaining truthful information
(announcement) ϕ, χ holds’.
2.2 Semantics
Let us go on to the semantics of LON. We call the tu-
ple hS, R,V i an epistemic model (or a Kripke model)
if the domain S is a nonempty set of states, the ac-
cessibility relation R is an equivalence relation on S
and V : Atom P (S) is a valuation function. The
set S is called domain of M and may be denoted
by D(M ). Subsequently, we define an epistemic
narrow-doxastic model (or simply en-model) M =
hS, R, Q,V i where the components of S, R and V are
the same as that of the epistemic model, and Q is a
binary relation on S such that Q R.
Definition 2.1 (Satisfaction relation). Given an en-
model M , a state s D(M ), and a formula ϕ
L
(KN⊕!)
, we define the satisfaction relation M , s |= ϕ
as follows:
M , s |= p iff s V (p),
M , s |= ¬ϕ iff M , s 6|= ϕ,
M , s |= ϕ χ iff M , s |= ϕ implies M , s |= χ,
M , s |= Kϕ iff for all x S : sRx implies M , x |= ϕ,
M , s |= Nϕ iff for all x S : sQx implies M , x |= ϕ,
M , s |= [ϕ]χ iff M
ϕ
,s |= χ,
M , s |= [ϕ]χ iff M
ϕ
,s |= χ,
M , s |= [.!.ϕ]χ iff M , s |= ϕ implies M
!ϕ
,s |= χ,
where the notations M
ϕ
, M
ϕ
and M
!ϕ
above re-
spectively indicate the en-models defined by M
ϕ
=
hS, R, Q
ϕ
,V i, M
ϕ
= hS, R, Q
ϕ
,V i and M
!ϕ
=
h[[ϕ]]
M
,R
!ϕ
,Q
!ϕ
,V
!ϕ
i with
[[ϕ]]
M
:= {x S | M , x |= ϕ},
R
!ϕ
:= R [[ϕ]]
M
×[[ϕ]]
M
,
Q
ϕ
:= Q {(s,t) R | s [[ϕ]]
M
or t [[ϕ]]
M
},
Q
!ϕ
:= Q [[ϕ]]
M
×[[ϕ]]
M
,
Q
ϕ
:= Q S × [[ϕ]]
M
,
V
!ϕ
(p) := V [[ϕ]]
M
(where p Atom).
Then we define the validity of a formula in a usual
way.
ICAART 2019 - 11th International Conference on Agents and Artificial Intelligence
248
Definition 2.2 (Valid). A formula ϕ is valid at M if
M ,s |= ϕ for any s D(M ), and we write M |= ϕ.
A formula ϕ is valid if M |= ϕ, for any en-model M ,
and we write |= ϕ.
We confirm that an en-model, which is modified
by announcement operators [ϕ],[ϕ] and [.!.ϕ], pre-
serves frame properties, i.e., R is an equivalence rela-
tion and the subset relation Q R.
Proposition 2.1 (Preserving frame properties). Let
ϕ L
(KN⊕!)
be any formula. If M = hS, R, Q,V i
is an en-model, then M
ϕ
= hS,R, Q
ϕ
,V i, M
ϕ
=
hS, R, Q
ϕ
,V i and M
!ϕ
= h[[ϕ]]
M
,R
!ϕ
,Q
!ϕ
,V
!ϕ
i are
also en-models.
Proof. What we wish to show is that (1) R
!ϕ
is an
equivalence relation (i.e., it satisfies reflexivity, Eu-
clidicity and transitivity), and (2) the subset relation
Q
!ϕ
R
!ϕ
, (3) the subset relation Q
ϕ
R and (4) the
subset relation Q
ϕ
R. We only treat one of (1) and
(3) in the following.
(1)-2 R
!ϕ
satisfies Euclidicity. Fix any x, y,z
[[ϕ]]
M
. Suppose xR
!ϕ
y and xR
!ϕ
z, and show yR
!ϕ
z.
Since R is Euclidean i.e., xRy and xRz jointly
imply yRz for all x,y, z S. By the assumption
x, y, z [[ϕ]]
M
S, we have x, y, z S and yRz.
so we get the goal R
!ϕ
is also Euclidean with
y, z X .
(3) Fix any (x, y) Q {(x, y) R | x [[ϕ]]
M
or y
[[ϕ]]
M
}, and we show (x,y) R. Suppose (x, y)
Q. Then we obtain (x, y) R with Q R. Suppose
(x, y) {(x,y) R | x [[ϕ]]
M
or y [[ϕ]]
M
}. So,
we obtain (x, y) R.
3 EXAMPLES OF
FORMALIZATION OF
NARROW-MINDED BELIEF
3.1 Comments of Knowledge and
Narrow-minded Belief Operators
Before moving on the topic of narrow-minded belief,
we add some comments on the general features of
knowledge operator K and accessibility relation R in
epistemic logics. Let us look at the epistemic model
hS, R,V i = h{w, v}, S
2
,V i where V (p) = {v} (that can
be regarded as an en-model M = h{w, v}, S
2
,,V i),
and the graphic form of this model is as follows.
M
w
99
tt
**
¬p
v
dd
p
In this model, at world w, the agent is ignorant about
ps truth-value. This is because the formula
b
Kp
b
K¬p, which intuitively means that the agent does not
know whether p, is true at w. As it implies, in epis-
temic logic, an arrow between states has a negative
meaning in general. In other words, van Ditmarsch
et al. state that “the more worlds an agent considers
possible, the less he believes, and vice versa. (van
Ditmarsch et al., 2008, p.55). The operator
b
K repre-
sents at least one arrow in an epistemic model. The
narrow-minded belief operator
b
N basically preserves
these features; nevertheless, we cannot say that ‘the
more worlds an agent considers possible, the less he
believes, and vice versa’ in case of the operator N
since the narrow-mind belief is affected by uncertain
information or even the agent’s imagination and may
be wrong. In other words, to express such capricious
belief, we introduce the operator N.
Additionally, we note on the frame property of
R and Q. The accessibility relation R represents the
accessibility relation for knowledge, and so we as-
sume that the agent is an introspective agent, i.e.,
R is an equivalence relation. Moreover, the for-
mulas of Kϕ ϕ, Kϕ KKϕ (positive introspec-
tion) and ¬Kϕ K¬Kϕ (negative introspection) are
valid at M where its accessibility relation is equiva-
lence relation. However, since Q represents a narrow-
minded belief, we do not assume the agent is intro-
spective since introspectiveness is based on some kind
of rationality, which is the exact opposite of narrow-
mindedness. That is why Q does not have any frame
property. By distinguishing these two accessibility re-
lations, we formally express the distinction between
knowledge and narrow-minded belief.
3.2 Formalizing Othello’s
Narrow-minded Belief
As mentioned in the introduction, our target, which
we consider and formalize, is Shakespeare’s Othello
as it depicts a typical case of the change in a person’s
delicate mental state. Its story depicts how the lives of
the four main characters (Othello, Desdemona, Iago
and Cassio) are woven together and driven by passion.
The following is the short summary of the play:
General in the Venetian military Othello was
recently married to a rich senator’s daughter
Desdemona. Although there is a great dispar-
ity of age between the two, they build a good
relationship of trust, and Othello and Desde-
mona love and believe each other from their
The Dynamics of Narrow-minded Belief
249
hearts. However, Othello’s trusted subordi-
nate Iago who secretly holds a deep grudge
against Othello tells him a rumor that Desde-
mona is having an affair with a young hand-
some soldier named Cassio. This causes Oth-
ello to feel uncertain towards his wife’s inno-
cence. Deepening Othello’s doubt against his
wife, Iago steals Desdemona’s handkerchief,
a present from Othello, and leads Cassio up
to find it. Using the handkerchief as proof,
Iago succeeds in convincing Othello that Des-
demona has engaged in an immoral relation-
ship with Cassio. Finally, Othello narrow-
mindedly believes what Iago has told him and
he feels great jealousy and anger towards his
wife. Even though Desdemona protests her in-
nocence, Othello, who is now mad with jeal-
ousy, kills his wife in a fit of passion. Follow-
ing her death, Desdemona’s servant confesses
that her mistress was innocent and that Iago
fabricated the story, which resulted in such a
tragedy. Othello comes to his senses and real-
izes his mistake, at which point he loses hope
and takes his own life.
Of course, this summary is extremely simplified and
actual tale is more intricately woven. There are at
least four main scenes in the story, which highlight
Othello’s narrow-minded belief, and we would like to
focus on these in this paper. The four main points are
as follows:
1. Othello believes Desdemona from the heart.
2. Iago spreads a bad rumor about Desdemona,
which causes doubt about her innocence in Oth-
ello’s mind.
3. Iago uses fake evidence (a handkerchief) to con-
vince Othello of Desdemona’s immoral actions
and he narrow-mindedly believes it.
4. A servant truthfully informs Othello that Desde-
mona is innocent.
Othello’s mind, including narrow-minded belief in
each of the four scenes, may be semantically modeled
as follows. We note that, in the graphic form of en-
models, the double circle indicates the actual state. In
addition, arrows of the straight line represent the line
of R and arrows of the dotted line represent that of Q.
Moreover, let an atomic proposition p to read ‘Desde-
mona is having an affair,’ and Atom = {p}.
(1) Othello deeply believes his wife. In the initial
stage, Othello, who was recently married, believes his
wife from the depth of his heart and does not doubt
her immorality. However, Othello does not have any
specific evidence that Desdemona is having an af-
fair and he does not actually know if she is innocent
or not at this stage. Therefore, the initial stage al-
ready includes some contradiction in his mind, i.e.,
he does not explicitly know if she is innocent, but
he narrow-mindedly believes her. Thus, the mental
state of Othello at the opening of the play may for-
mally be expressed by en-model M = hS,R, Q,V i =
h{s,t}, S
2
,{(s,s)}, {p 7→ {t}}i. Therefore, we may
say that, at this stage, formulas
b
Kp
b
K¬p and N¬p
are valid at M .
s
::
--
tt
**
¬p
t
cc
p
Figure 1: M .
(2) Iago spreads a bad rumor about Desdemona,
which leads to doubts in Othello’s mind. After
Iago tells Othello a bad rumor ([p]) about Desde-
mona, he begins to doubt his wife. In other words,
he is now unsure about her constancy and does not
know if she is innocent or not. Separately from Oth-
ello’s narrow-minded belief, his state of knowledge
remains unchanged since he has not obtained any new
truthful information and can only go by Iago’s story
in which his wife is accused of infidelity. Then the
mental state of Othello at the second stage of the
play may formally be expressed by en-model M
p
=
hS, R, Q
p
,V i = h{s,t}, S
2
,S
2
,{p 7→ {t}}i, where the
formula
b
Np
b
N¬p is now valid at this en-model. This
formula represents a confusion in his mind about his
wife’s innocence.
s
::
--
tt
**
¬p
t
cc
qq
44
jj
p
Figure 2: M
p
.
(3) Iago uses fake evidence to convince Othello
of Desdemona’s immorality. At this stage of the
play, Iago attempts to deceive his superior, Oth-
ello, by using fake evidence (Desdemona’s hand-
kerchief) to pretend she spent her time with Cas-
sio, and Othello is completely taken in. Conse-
quently, Othello completely loses his self-control, and
strongly and narrow-mindedly believes that his wife
is having an affair with Cassio. This is also rep-
resented by en-model M
pp
= hS, R, Q
pp
,V i =
h{s,t}, S
2
,{(t,t),(s,t)}, {p 7→ {t}}i. Formally, in his
mind, the formula
b
Np is valid at this en-model, but
b
N¬p is not anymore. Let us remind the reader that in
s
::
tt
**
¬p
t
cc
qq
44
p
Figure 3: M
pp
.
ICAART 2019 - 11th International Conference on Agents and Artificial Intelligence
250
the case of the operator
b
N, it does not mean that if the
number of arrows is reduced, then the agent’s igno-
rance is reduced.
(4) A servant truthfully informs that Desde-
mona is innocent. In the last scene of the play,
Desdemona’s faithful servant truthfully tells the
fact that Desdemona is innocent, implying that
Othello’s narrow-minded belief regarding his wife
is completely erroneous. Othello faces such a
surprising fact and he is heart-broken by the
confession. This is represented by en-model
M
pp!¬p
= h[[¬p]]
M
pp
,R
!¬p
,Q
pp!¬p
,V
!¬p
i =
h{s},{(s, s)},
/
0,
/
0}i. Formally, by the truthful in-
formation of ¬p, a state t where p holds is elim-
inated, and as a result, while the agent (Othello)
knows ¬p (his wife is innocent), the arrow of narrow-
minded belief is empty. This means that he narrow-
mindedly believes everything even if it is a contra-
diction M
pp!¬p
|= , i.e., he is going crazy. As a
result, the tragedy ends with the suicide of Othello in
the final scene.
s
::
¬p
t
Figure 4: M
pp!¬p
.
4 HILBERT-SYSTEM FOR LON
We move on the topic of a proof theory for LON.
Hilbert-system for LON (LON), is defined in Ta-
ble 1. Axioms (4) and (5) indicate what we call pos-
itive introspection and negative introspection, respec-
tively. Axiom (K&N) indicates a relation of knowl-
edge and narrow-mined belief, in which if the agent
knows something, he/she also narrow-mindedly be-
lieves. This implies that narrow-minded belief is one
of the bases of our knowledge, and this view of be-
lief and knowledge can be supported by philosophers
and/or psychologists like Hume and Damasio, as dis-
cussed in the introduction. Axioms (RA) are called
reduction axioms. Through the reduction axioms and
rules, each theorem of LON may be reduced into a
theorem of the language L
(KN)
which will be shown
in Section 5.
We provide some basic definitions and properties
for proofs in the next section.
Definition 4.1 (Derivable). A derivation in LON con-
sists of a sequence of formulas of L
(KN⊕!)
each of
which is an instance of an axiom or is the result of
applying an inference rule to formula(s) that occur
earlier. If ϕ is the last formula in a derivation in LON,
then ϕ is derivable in LON, and we write `
LON
ϕ (or
just ` ϕ).
Let ϕ be a formula of L
(KN⊕!)
and Γ be a subset of
languageKakko. Then, ϕ is derivable from Γ (Γ `
LON
ϕ) if there exists a finite subset Γ
0
of Γ such that `
LON
V
Γ
0
ϕ.
Proposition 4.1. Let ϕ, χ, ψ be arbitrary formulas of
L
(KN⊕!)
. Then the following holds.
1. `
LON
[ϕ](χψ) ([ϕ]χ[ϕ]ψ) (where
{⊕,, .!.})
2. `
LON
ϕ χ implies `
LON
[ψ]ϕ
[ψ]χ (where {⊕, , .!.})
3. `
LON
ϕ χ implies `
LON
2ϕ
2χ (where 2 {K,N}
Definition 4.2 (Substitution). The substitution for
formula ϕ
p
χ
means p appearing in a formula ϕ is
Table 1: Hilbert-system for LON : LON.
Axioms for knowledge andnarrowminded belief
(taut) all instantiations of
propositional tautologies
(K
K
) K(ϕ χ) (Kϕ Kχ)
(K
N
) N(ϕ χ) (Nϕ Nχ)
(T) Kϕ ϕ
(4) Kϕ KKϕ
(5) ¬Kϕ K¬Kϕ
(K&N) Kϕ Nϕ
Inference Rules
(MP) From ϕ and ϕ χ, infer χ
(NecK) From ϕ, infer Kϕ
(NecN) From ϕ, infer Nϕ
(Nec[]) From ϕ, infer [χ]ϕ
where {, ,.!.}
Reduction Axioms for []
(RA1) [ψ]p p
(RA2) [ψ]¬ϕ ¬[ψ]ϕ
(RA3) [ψ](ϕ χ) ([ψ]ϕ [ψ]χ)
(RA4) [ψ]Kϕ K[ψ]ϕ
(RA5) [ψ]Nϕ N[ψ]ϕ
(ψ K[ψ]ϕ) K(ψ [ψ]ϕ)
Reduction Axioms for []
(RA1) [ψ]p p
(RA2) [ψ]¬ϕ ¬[ψ]ϕ
(RA3) [ψ](ϕ χ) ([ψ]ϕ [ψ]χ)
(RA4) [ψ]Kϕ K[ψ]ϕ
(RA5) [ψ]Nϕ N(ψ [ψ]ϕ)
Reduction Axioms for [.!.]
(RA!1) [.!.ψ]p (ψ p)
(RA!2) [.!.ψ]¬ϕ (ψ ¬[.!.ψ]ϕ)
(RA!3) [.!.ψ](ϕ χ) ([.!.ψ]ϕ [.!.ψ]χ)
(RA!4) [.!.ψ]Kϕ (ψ K[.!.ψ]ϕ)
(RA!5) [.!.ψ]Nϕ (ψ N(ψ [.!.ψ]ϕ))
The Dynamics of Narrow-minded Belief
251
replaced by χ, and defined as follows:
q
p
χ
:= q (if q 6= p),
q
p
χ
:= χ (if q = p),
(ψ)
p
χ
:= (ψ
p
χ
),
(ψ
1
ψ
2
)
p
χ
:= (ψ
1
p
χ
) (ψ
2
p
χ
),
([ψ
1
]ψ
2
)
p
χ
:= [ψ
1
](ψ
2
p
χ
).
where , K, N} and {,, !}.
Proposition 4.2. Let {, , !}. If `
LON
ϕ χ,
then `
LON
ψ
p
ϕ
ψ
p
χ
for any ϕ, χ, ψ L
(KN⊕!)
and p Atom.
Proof. Fix any ϕ, χ L
(KN⊕!)
and p Atom. Sup-
pose `
LON
ϕ χ. Then we show `
LON
ψ
p
ϕ
ψ
p
χ
By induction on ψ L
(KN⊕!)
.
5 COMPLETENESS
Let us move onto a proof of the completeness theorem
of LON with a similar argument in (van Ditmarsch
et al., 2008, Section 5).
5.1 Semantic Completeness of LON
0
Let the language L
(KN)
be our formal lan-
guage L
(KN⊕!)
without announcement operators
([],[] and [.!.]). For an en-model M and s
D(M ) and ϕ L
(KN)
, the satisfaction relation
M ,s |= ϕ is naturally defined by following the def-
inition in Section 2. Additionally, Hilbert-system
LON
0
is also generated by rejecting the reduction ax-
ioms and inference rules of (Nec[]), (Nec) and
(Nec[.!.]) in Table 1. Note that definitions of the
derivation and derivability of LON
0
are given in the
same manner as that of LON in Definition 4.1.
Theorem 5.1 (Soundness of LON
0
). For any formula
ϕ L
(KN)
,
`
LON
0
ϕ implies |= ϕ.
Proof. Fix any ϕ L
(KN)
such that ϕ is derivable
in LON
0
. We show that ϕ is valid by induction on
the height of the derivation. In the base case, the
derivation height is 0 i.e., it consists of only an ax-
iom. Therefore, we show the validity of each axiom
of LON.
A direct proof of the completeness theorem of LON
0
can be shown in a usual manner with Lindenbaum’s
lemma.
Theorem 5.2 (Completeness for LON
0
w.r.t. the se-
mantics of L
(KN)
). For any ϕ L
(KN)
, the following
holds:
|= ϕ implies `
LON
0
ϕ.
5.2 Semantic Completeness of LON
Based on the completeness theorem of LON
0
, we ex-
pand the discussion to the completeness of LON. A
proof of the completeness theorem of LON is given
in this section by the reduction method whose ba-
sic idea was introduced in the previous work (Plaza,
1989, Theorem 2.7). The essential idea of this method
is based on the fact that every formula in L
(KN⊕!)
is
reducible into a formula in L
(KN)
which will be shown
in Lemma 5.3.
Remark 5.1. We note that reduction axioms for se-
quential announcement operators e.g.,
(RA!6) [.!.χ][.!.ψ]ϕ [.!.(χ [.!.χ]ψ)]ϕ
are not included since, without them, any formula
with announcement operators can be reducible. It is
known that there are at least two strategies to reduce
a formula with announcement operators into a for-
mula without any such operator. Let us consider the
formula [!p][!q]r (i). One approach, we may call
it ‘outermost strategy’, focuses on the outermost oc-
currence of announcement operator, for example [!p]
of the above formula (i). Following this strategy, an
axiom like (RA!6) is required for reducing the for-
mula. By using (RA!6), we may obtain [!(p[!p]q)]q.
Then (RA!1) becomes applicable, and so we obtain
the formula which does not include any announce-
ment operator but is equivalent to the initial formula.
This approach is introduced by (van Ditmarsch et al.,
2008). The other strategy may be called ‘innermost
strategy’ and focuses on the innermost occurrence of
announcement operator, for example [!q] of (i). Thus,
by applying (RA!1) to the innermost occurrence i.e.,
[!q]r, we obtain [!p](q r). After that, (RA!3) and
(RA!1) are subsequently applicable, and so we ob-
tain the formula without any announcement operator
but equivalent to the initial formula of (i). The latter
strategy does not require reduction axioms for reduc-
ing sequential announcement operators into a single.
Therefore, we employ this strategy to avoid introduc-
ing many and messy axioms.
1
The idea of this inner-
most strategy was introduced by (van Benthem et al.,
2006), and (van Benthem, 2011, p.54). Furthermore,
an attentive proof for reducibility of a formula of Dy-
namic logic into a formula of standard modal logic
1
If we follow the outermost strategy, six additional ax-
ioms (e.g, axioms for reducing combination of [A][B]
and [.!.A][B] etc.) are required.
ICAART 2019 - 11th International Conference on Agents and Artificial Intelligence
252
by using the innermost strategy is given in (Aucher,
2003, Proposition 3.3.5).
2
At first, we treat the soundness theorem of it which
is straightforward.
Theorem 5.3 (Soundness of LON). For any formula
ϕ L
(KN⊕!)
,
`
LON
ϕ implies |= ϕ.
Proof. For the soundness theorem of LON, it suffices
to show the validity of reduction axioms, additional
axioms to that of LON
0
and additional inference rules
(Nec[]),(Nec[]) and (Nec[.!.]). The validity of ad-
ditional rules and axioms are also easily shown by fol-
lowing semantics of LON.
Next, we give some definitions and lemmas for
proof of the completeness.
Definition 5.1 (Length). The length function
` : L
(KN⊕!)
N is inductively defined as follows:
`(p) := 1, `(Nϕ) := 1 + `(ϕ),
`(¬ϕ) := 1 + `(ϕ), `([ϕ]χ) := (5 + `(ϕ))
`(χ)
,
`(ϕ χ) := 1 + `(ϕ) + `(χ), `([ϕ]χ) := (5 + `(ϕ))
`(χ)
,
`(Kϕ) := 1 + `(ϕ), `([.!.ϕ]χ) := (5 + `(ϕ))
`(χ)
.
With these settings, we may show the following
lemma.
Lemma 5.1. Let be , or !. Then for all reduction
axioms [ϕ]χ ψ, `([ϕ]χ) > `(ψ) holds.
Proof. We only confirm the following case.
Case of (RA 5). The less-than relation
`(N[ψ]ϕ (ψ K[ψ]ϕ) K(ψ [ψ]ϕ)) <
`([χ]Nϕ) holds by the following equations:
`(N[ψ]ϕ (ψ K[ψ]ϕ) K(ψ [ψ]ϕ))
= `(N[ψ]ϕ ¬(ψ K[ψ]ϕ) K(ψ [ψ]ϕ))
= 2 + `(N[ψ]ϕ) + `(ϕ K[ψ]ϕ) + `(Kϕ K[ψ]ϕ)
= 8 + `([ψ]ϕ) + `(ϕ) + `([ψ]ϕ) + `(ϕ) + `([ψ]ϕ)
= 8 + 2 · `(ϕ) + 3 · (5 + `(ψ))
`(ϕ)
Then we can prove that `([ψ]Nϕ) = k
1+`(ϕ)
>
8 + 2 · `(ϕ) + 3 · k
`(ϕ)
(where k = (5 + `(ψ)) 6)
holds.
3
2
We add one more comment for a technical difference
between the two strategies. In the outermost strategy of
public announcement logic, we need to include axiom like
(RA!6) to reduce sequential announcement operators into a
single, but the inference rule of (Nec[!]) is derivable. On
the other hand, the rule is indispensable in the case of the
innermost strategy, instead of economizing the number of
axioms.
3
Let `(ϕ) = n and f
n
(k) k
n+1
3k
n
2n 8. Then
obviously f
n
(k) = k
n
(k 3) 2n 8 > 0 for k 6 for any
fixed n 1, as well as for fixed n 1 for any k 6.
Lemma 5.2. For any p Atom, ϕ, χ, ψ L
(KN⊕!)
,
if `(ϕ) > `(χ) and ψ
p
ϕ
6= ψ
p
χ
, then `(ψ
p
ϕ
) >
`(ψ
p
χ
) holds.
Proof. Fix any p Atom and ϕ, χ L
(KN⊕!)
. Then
assume `(ϕ) > `(χ). We conduct the proof by induc-
tion on ψ L
(KN⊕!)
.
Case of ψ is of the form ψ
1
ψ
2
. Assume (ψ
1
ψ
2
)
p
ϕ
6= (ψ
1
ψ
2
)
p
χ
. We show `((ψ
1
ψ
2
)
p
ϕ
) > `((ψ
1
ψ
2
)
p
χ
). Therefore, it suf-
fices to show `(ψ
1
p
ϕ
) + `(ψ
2
p
ϕ
) > `(ψ
1
p
χ
) +
`(ψ
2
p
χ
). From the assumption, we obtain that
at least one of C
1
and C
2
satisfies ψ
i
p
ϕ
6=
ψ
i
p
χ
. Without loss of generality, assume that
ψ
1
p
ϕ
6= ψ
1
p
χ
. By induction hypothesis, we ob-
tain `(ψ
1
p
ϕ
) > `(ψ
1
p
χ
). Therefore, no mat-
ter whether ψ
2
p
ϕ
6= ψ
2
p
χ
or not, we obtain the
goal.
Other cases are similar to the above.
Definition 5.2. `
0
: L
(KN⊕!)
N is defined as fol-
lows.
`
0
(ϕ) :=
0 if ϕ L
(KN)
`(ϕ) otherwise
Lemma 5.3 (Reduction lemma). For any ϕ
L
(KN⊕!)
, there exists ψ L
(KN)
such that `
LON
ϕ
ψ.
Proof. By induction on `
0
(ϕ). We only treat the fol-
lowing case.
Case: `
0
(ϕ) > 0. In this case, ϕ L
(KN⊕!)
in-
cludes at least one subformula which is of the
form [χ
1
]χ
2
(where {⊕, , !} and χ
1
L
(KN⊕!)
,χ
2
L
(KN)
). On the other hand, there
is a reduction axiom which has the form of
[χ
1
]χ
2
χ
3
, and let this reduction axiom be
(RA). The formula ϕ is equal to D
p
[χ
1
]χ
2
and
ϕ
0
is equal to D
p
χ
3
for some D L
(KN⊕!)
, and
so fix such D. Then we may obtain the following
derivation.
1. ` [χ
1
]χ
2
χ
3
(RA*)
2. ` ϕ ϕ
0
1 and Proposition 4.2
3. ` ϕ
0
ψ Induction hypothesis
4. ` (ϕ ϕ
0
) ((ϕ
0
ψ) (ϕ ψ)) (taut)
5. ` ϕ ψ 2,3 and 4 with (MP)
The Dynamics of Narrow-minded Belief
253
where ϕ = D
p
[χ
1
]χ
2
and ϕ
0
= D
p
χ
3
. Induc-
tion hypothesis in the above derivation is applica-
ble, since the less-than relation `
0
(D
p
[χ
1
]χ
2
) >
`
0
(D
p
χ
3
) holds by Lemma 5.1 and Lemma 5.2.
Actually, Lemma 5.3 is the core of the proof of the
completeness theorem. Through this, we may easily
show the theorem as follows.
Theorem 5.4 (Completeness of LON w.r.t. the se-
mantics of L
(KN⊕!)
). For any formula ϕ L
(KN⊕!)
,
the following holds:
|= ϕ implies `
LON
ϕ.
Proof. Fix any ϕ L
(KN⊕!)
such that |= ϕ. By
Lemma 5.3, we obtain `
LON
ϕ χ for some χ
L
(KN)
. Then consider such χ L
(KN)
. By Theo-
rem 5.3 (the soundness of LON), we obtain |= ϕ χ.
With the assumption |= ϕ, we have |= χ. Next, by
Theorem 5.2 (the completeness of LON
0
), we obtain
`
LON
0
χ, and so `
LON
χ trivially holds; therefore, we
obtain `
LON
ϕ with `
LON
ϕ χ again. That is what
we desired.
6 RELATED WORKS
In this section, we introduce some related epis-
temic/doxastic logics. An epistemic logic for implicit
and explicit belief by (Vel
´
azquez-Quesada, 2014) is
perhaps the closest concept we can find to that of
LON. This logic is based on the logic of awareness
logic (van Benthem and Vel
´
azquez-Quesada, 2010),
and it distinguishes the sense of belief into two, im-
plicit and explicit belief, to avoid the logical omni-
science in epistemic logic. A traditional approach
to mix knowledge and belief operators, sometimes
called epistemic-doxastic logic (e.g., see (Voorbraak,
1993)), is another system similar to ours since K and
N of LON may be interpreted as a mixture of these
two different human tendencies.
One of differences between LON and the above
existing works may relate to the definition of the sat-
isfaction relation of LON:
M , s |= [ϕ]χ iff M
ϕ
,s |= χ,
where Q
ϕ
:= Q {(s,t) R | s [[ϕ]]
M
or t [[ϕ]]
M
}.
Here, we include a mechanism of adding arrows i.e.,
a mechanism in which some of the information may
confuse the agent.
In addition, there are some other attempts to in-
troduce a distinction in our belief/knowledge from
a different point of view. Intuitionistic epistemic
logic (Artemov and Protopopescu, 2014; Williamson,
1992) is one of them; this epistemic logic is based
on intuitionistic logic, which distinguishes knowledge
into two: standard knowledge, which normal epis-
temic logics treat and knowledge in the strict sense.
In other words, this aims at introducing a distinction
in knowledge, more strict and rational knowledge and
not strict knowledge, which is an opposite perspec-
tive to our attempt, which introduced a distinction be-
tween belief with passion and knowledge.
There are also some logics which deal with human
emotion; for example (Lorini and Schwarzentruber,
2011) and (Dastani and Lorini, 2012). We may, for
the further development, need to consider relevance
to these existing logics about emotion.
7 CONCLUSION AND FURTHER
DIRECTIONS
We introduced logic of narrow-minded belief (LON),
a variant of dynamic epistemic logic. This aims to
formally express a human’s passionate and narrow-
minded belief, and as an example of the application
of LON, we formalized Shakespeare’s play Othello.
Philosophers and neuropsychologists believe that pas-
sion, or belief affected by passion, is an indispensable
factor and even a basis for our reason. Without pas-
sion or emotions, human intelligence may be never
realized. Therefore, we hope that our attempt in the
present work will contribute to formal expressions of
the human mind.
It may be possible to further develop our attempt
in various directions. For example, we did not re-
gard the problem of the logical omniscience; the logic
of awareness is one of the candidates to be added
to LON, as it is difficult to interpret the meaning of
awareness in the context of passion. Another inter-
esting feature that should be considered and added
to LON is ‘a lie’ as it pertains to dynamic epistemic
logic by van Ditmarsch (van Ditmarsch, 2011). Actu-
ally, Iago’s rumor should be regarded as a lie, as our
passion or narrow-mindedness is easily affected by
such dubious information. Therefore, it might be in-
teresting to consider these aspects in future researches
regarding the logic of passion.
ACKNOWLEDGMENT
The authors thank the anonymous reviewers for their
careful reading of our manuscript and their many in-
sightful comments. This work was supported by JST
ICAART 2019 - 11th International Conference on Agents and Artificial Intelligence
254
CREST Grant Number JPMJCR1513 and JSPS kaken
17H02258.
REFERENCES
Artemov, S. and Protopopescu, T. (2014). Intuitionistic
epistemic logic. Computer Science Technical Reports,
Paper401.
Aucher, G. (2003). A combination system for update logic
and belief revision. Master’s thesis, University of Am-
sterdam.
Damasio, A. (1994). Descartes’ Error: Emotion, Reason,
and the Human Brain. Avon books, New York.
Dastani, M. and Lorini, E. (2012). A logic of emotions:
from appraisal to coping. Proceedings of the 11th
International Conference on Autonomous Agents and
Multiagent Systems, 2:1133–1140.
Hume, D. (1739). A Treatise of Human Nature. Oxford
University Press.
Lorini, E. and Schwarzentruber, F. (2011). A logic for rea-
soning about counterfactual emotions. Artificial Intel-
ligence, 175(3-4):814–847.
Plaza, J. (1989). Logic of public communications. Proceed-
ings of the 4th International Symposium on Method-
ologies for Intellingent Systems: Poster Session Pro-
gram, pages 201–216.
van Benthem, J. (2011). Logical Dynamic of Information
and Interaction. Cambridge University Press, Cam-
bridge.
van Benthem, J., van Eijck, J., and Kooi, B. (2006). Logic of
communications and change. Information and Com-
putation, 204(11).
van Benthem, J. and Vel
´
azquez-Quesada, F. R. (2010). The
dynamics of awareness. Synthese, 177(5):5–27.
van Ditmarsch, H. (2011). The Ditmarsch tale of wonders-
the dynamics of lying. Reasoning About Other Minds:
Logical and Cognitive Perspectives, 65.
van Ditmarsch, H., Hoek, W., and Kooi, B. (2008). Dy-
namic Epistemic Logic. Springer Verlag Gmbh, Dor-
drecht.
Vel
´
azquez-Quesada, F. R. (2014). Dynamic epistemic logic
for implicit and explicit beliefs. Journal of Logic, Lan-
guage and Information, 23(2):107–140.
Voorbraak, F. (1993). As far as I know—epistemic logic and
uncertainty. Phd thesis, Utrecht University.
Williamson, T. (1992). On intuitionistic modal epistemic
logic. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 21(1):63–89.
The Dynamics of Narrow-minded Belief
255