The Principle of Ethics behind the Definitions of Corruption
Sunaryo
Paramadina University Jakarta, Indonesia.
Keywords: Corruption, Deontology, Teleology, Ethics
Abstract: In this article, I will analyze the main criteria of corrupt action and the ethical view behind the definitions of
corruption. I analyze some definitions, among which belong to Transparency International, The Asian
Development Bank, The Korean Independent Commission against Corruption, and the Indonesian Act of
Corruption Crime. I show that generally, there are three main criteria to identify corrupt action, first the misuse
of authority, second the evidence of grant seeking, and third is detrimental to the economy or finance of the
state. In analyzing the ethical view, I use two schools of ethics i.e., deontological ethics and teleological ethics.
Based on this view, I conclude that behind the definitions of corruption, we find that teleological ethics is
more dominant than deontological ethics. Perhaps, it is easy to understand why this basis of view is used in
understanding corruption. The most important is because it is practical and easier for identifying corrupt
action.
1 INTRODUCTION
In this article, I will explore the criteria to understand
why an action is seen as a corrupt action. In this
article, I also want to see the ethical perspective
behind the definitions of corruption. To do this study,
I need, firstly look at the definitions of corruption
stated by some conventions and acts. I analyze the
main criteria to decide an action as corrupt. To see the
principle of ethics in the definitions of corruption, I
utilize two ethical perspectives as an approach i.e.,
deontological ethics as formulated by Immanuel Kant
(1724-1804) and teleological ethics, especially in
perspective of utilitarianism as formulated by Jeremy
Bentham (1748-1832). Through this study, we can
see what the main criteria of corruption and the
ethical perspective behind the definitions are.
2 METHODOLOGY
This study will see the definitions of corruption as the
main focus. I will refer to some definitions as stated
in conventions, documents, and acts, like United
Nations Convention Against Corruption, the
document in OECD, Transparency International, The
Asian Development Bank, The Korean Independent
Commission against Corruption, and the Act of
Crime Action of Corruption in Indonesia. Through
this exploration, we will see the similarities and the
differences among definitions. So, based on this
exploration, we can see the main criteria of corrupt
action by that the definition is established.
Then we come to see the ethical perspective
behind the definitions of corruption. We use two
schools of ethics in analyzing the content of the
definition of corruption i.e., deontological ethics and
teleological ethics. Deontological ethics is a view of
ethics that believes that a good thing is good because
it is good in itself. It is good not because of its good
implication or its good consequence. So, it is good
because it is good in itself (Kant, 2002: 10).
"The goodwill is good not through what it effects
or accomplishes, not through its efficacy for attaining
any intended end, but only through its willing, i.e.,
good in itself, and considered for itself, without
comparison, it is to be estimated far higher than
anything that could be brought about by it in favor of
any inclination, or indeed, if you prefer, of the sum of
all inclination. then it would shine like a jewel for
itself, as something that has its full worth in itself.”
Whereas teleological ethics is the opposite of
deontological ethics. This view sees the good thing
because of its good implications. The popular jargon
in this ethics is the greatest happiness for the greatest
number (Mill, 1906:9).
138
Sunaryo, .
The Principle of Ethics behind the Definitions of Corruption.
DOI: 10.5220/0009401201380142
In Proceedings of the 1st International Conference on Anti-Corruption and Integrity (ICOACI 2019), pages 138-142
ISBN: 978-989-758-461-9
Copyright
c
2020 by SCITEPRESS – Science and Technology Publications, Lda. All rights reserved
2.1 Deontological Ethics
Deontological ethics most refers to an eighteenth
German philosopher, namely Immanuel Kant (1724-
1804). In understanding the concept of the good, he
said that something could be called good because it is
good in itself. It is called as good not because of its
implication or its consequence, but because it is
indeed good in itself (Kant, 2002: 10). In this view,
human beings must do this good thing as the
categorical imperative. This differs from the
hypothetical imperative. In hypothetical imperative,
an obligation must be fulfilled if we want to achieve
what promised as a consequence. For example, I must
drink medicine if I want to be free from sickness.
Thus, if we don't want it, medicine drinking is not an
obligation. Whereas categorical imperative is an
obligation, we cannot avoid as human beings. In other
words, the categorical imperative is an unconditional
imperative (Kant, 2002:31).
According to Kant, the categorical imperative
statement is "act morally!". As human beings, we
cannot avoid this imperative in terms that we must act
morally. Then how do we act morally? The moral
action, according to Kant, is if the action could be
universalized and based on the perspective the human
beings end in itself, not as means (Kant, 2002: 37;
45).
The principle of universalization is a kind of way
to know whether the action could be seen as good or
not. This is like the principle of the golden rule, if you
like to be respected, then respect the others! So,
respect and honest action are good because they could
be universalized. Other people and we must agree that
those actions are good in itself. Then we can conclude
that this kind of action is a moral obligation in terms
of the categorical imperative. Everyone must respect
and be honest with each other unconditionally. We
need to underline the importance of the motive of the
actor to do this action. Human beings are obliged to
respect and be honest because they are an obligation.
If they do the same actions with the motive of a good
impact, then we cannot categorize the action as
ethical. For example, if a merchant is honest with the
motive to attract the attention of consumers, this
action is not ethical, according to Kant (Sandel,
2009:111-113).
The next principle is that moral action must place
human beings as an end in itself, not as a means. The
action to respect or care for others, for example, if
someone does these actions with the motive that the
other will respect or care for himself, we can
categorize these actions as a means to achieve other
things. People do not do these actions because they
are obligations to human beings. The action to respect
and care is, in itself, an unconditional obligation.
Based on this interpretation, deontological ethics
conceptualize moral action as a good thing in itself.
The action is good, not because of the implication or
consequence.
2.2 Teleological Ethics
Principally, teleological ethics is the opposite of
deontological ethics. These ethics see good action by
its implication or impact. Utilitarianism is one of
these ethics. In utilitarianism, something is good if the
impact is good. If the impact is bad, then the action is
bad (Mill, 1906:10). So, what we must see in this
ethics is the aspect of utility or benefit (Bentham,
1823: 2). The most popular jargon in this ethics is the
greatest good for the greatest number (Marry,
2003:1). Based on this principle, we categorize
utilitarianism as teleological ethics because the good
thing must be measured by the impact and
consequence.
These ethics concentrate basically on impact or
result. For most people, utilitarianism is very popular.
Practically, if we must decide an option, most people
will consider the impact of options. They will choose
the option having the most benefit for the most
people. And rationally, they will avoid the riskiest
option for most people. Bentham (1823: 1) said that
“Nature placed mankind under the governance of two
sovereign masters, pain and pleasure. It is for them
alone to point out what we ought to do, as well as to
determinate what we shall do. …They govern us in
all we do, in all we say, in all we think…” At some
level, we categorize this perspective as teleological.
Then, through these two ethical perspectives, we will
analyze the content of the definitions of corruption.
3 THE DEFINITIONS OF
CORRUPTION
Firstly, we need to see the etymological term for
corruption. Etymologically, as a noun, corruption, in
material things, especially dead bodies, means "act of
becoming putrid, dissolution, decay;" and of the soul
and morals, etc., means "spiritual contamination,
depravity, wickedness,"
(https://www.etymonline.com/word/corruption). As
a verb, corrumpere means in mid-14c., "deprave
morally, pervert from good to bad;" an in late 14c.,
"contaminate, impair the purity of; seduce or violate
(a woman); debase or render impure (a language) by
The Principle of Ethics behind the Definitions of Corruption
139
alterations or innovations; influence by a bribe or
other wrong motive"
(https://www.etymonline.com/word/corrupt). From
this etymological term, we can see the meaning of
corruption as making a good thing bad (Priyono,
2018: 22-23).
Bo Rothstein and Aiysha Varraich define
corruption as the opposite of impartiality like
clientelism, patronage, patrimonialism, particularism,
and state capture (Priyono, 2018: 26-27). Based on
this understanding, corruption is an action that is not
in line with the principle of objectivity and fairness.
The inclination to one thing instead of another thing
which is proper and fits is a corrupt action in this
meaning. Of course, this meaning of corruption is
very broad. In the terminological definition, we need
to specify the meaning of corruption.
However, we found that some conventions and
documents face difficulty in defining corruption
precisely. Some of them do not give a specific
terminological definition. United Nations Convention
against Corruption is among them. Instead of
establishing the definition, it defines corruption by
giving concrete actions which are categorized as
corrupt, like "bribery of national public officials",
"bribery of foreign public officials and officials of
public international organizations", and including
“embezzlement, misappropriation and other
diversion of property by a public official” and
obstruction of justice (UN Convention, 2004: 17-18).
Based on these provisions, the convention tries to
define international standards of why corruption is
criminalized by prescribing specific offenses rather
than through a generic definition (OECD, 2007: 19).
The OECD and the Council of Europe are doing
the same. They do not define the whatness of
"corruption." They prefer to establish the offenses for
a range of corrupt behavior (OECD, 2007: 19). The
OECD Convention establishes the meaning of
corruption as the offense of bribery of foreign public
officials, while the Council of Europe Convention as
trading in influence, and bribing domestic and foreign
public officials (OECD, 2007: 19). Based on this
meaning, we find a broad range of corrupt activities.
The difficulty in defining corruption is because there
are many manifestations of corrupt activities. Culture,
social, and political context contributes significantly
to a variety of the definition of corruption. Within
these definitions, there is no consensus about what
specific acts should be included or excluded.
But, one frequently-used definition of corruption
is the “abuse of public or private office for personal
gain” (OECD, 2007: 19). This definition covers a
broad range of corrupt activities either done by public
or private. Generally, the public office is more often
understood as corrupt agents if they do abuse of
authority than private. As we can see in Transparency
International definition: "Corruption involves
behavior on the part of officials in the public sector,
whether politicians or civil servants, in which they
improperly and unlawfully enrich themselves, or
those close to them, by the misuse of the public power
entrusted to them" (OECD, 2007: 20). On the
website, Transparency International defines
corruption as "The abuse of entrusted power for
private gain. Corruption can be classified as grand,
petty and political, depending on the amounts of
money lost and the sector where it occurs”
(https://www.transparency.org/glossary/term/corrupt
ion). We can also see in the Korean Independent
Commission against Corruption which promotes the
reporting of "any public official involving abuse of
position or authority of violation of the law in
connection with official duties for the purpose of
seeking grants for himself or a third party" (OECD,
2007: 20)
The wider actor of corruption is found in the
definition of the Asian Development Bank. They
define: "Corruption involves behavior on the part of
officials in the public and private sectors, in which
they improperly and unlawfully enrich themselves
and/or those close to them, or induce others to do so,
by misusing the position in which they are placed"
(OECD, 2007: 20, see also
https://www.adb.org/documents/anticorruption-
policy). In terms of the wider actor can also be found
in the Indonesian Act of corruption crime number 31,
1999, junto Act number 20, 2001, in articles 2 and 3.
The act defines corruption as "Any person who
unlawfully commits acts of enriching himself or
others or a corporation that can be detrimental to the
country's finances or the country's economy…” and
“Any person who aims to benefit himself or someone
else or a corporation, misuse the authority,
opportunity, or means available to him because of his
position that can harm the country's finances and the
country's economy.”
Overall, based on those definitions, we can find
some key terms of corrupt action like "unlawful,"
"enriching himself," "enriching third party,"
"detrimental to the finance or economy of the
country," and "misusing position." So, if we
summarize the definitions, corrupt action must
contain unlawful, including misuse of position, the
motive of seeking grants, and detrimental to finance
and economy of the country. And the actors of
corruption can come from public officials or private
ICOACI 2019 - International Conference on Anti-Corruption and Integrity
140
officials. But one another has a different emphasis.
We can specify the definitions one by one.
In the Indonesian Act of Corruption Crime, we see
the definition focuses on the misuse of position by
either public or private officials that is detrimental to
the economy of the country. In this definition, we can
identify the orientation to impact or consequence. We
can also identify unlawful action or misuse of
position in this definition. The emphasis on lawful
obligation may be found here. But we see then that
the misuse must have a motive of grant seeking or
enriching himself or third party. We cannot identify
this as a deontological view of ethics. Based on this
specification, the misuse of position which doesn't
enrich the actors and third parties cannot be
categorized as corruption.
In the definition of the Asian Development Bank,
it emphasizes the misuse of authority to seek grant
done by public officials and private officials. The
definition doesn't make detrimental to the economy of
the state as criteria in corrupt action. It more
underlines the criteria of misuse and grants seeking.
In some way, this definition is similar to
Transparency International and The Korean
Commission Independent against Corruption’s
definition. Except that the two later don’t make
private officials as actor underlined in the definition
of corruption.
Table 1: The Definitions of Corruption
Definition Actor Criteria I Criteria II Criteria III
Indonesian Act of
Corruption Crime
Public and Private
Officials
Misuse of
Authority
Grant seeking Detrimental to Economy and
Finance of the State
The Asian
Development Bank
Public and Private
Officials
Misuse of
Authority
Grant seeking -
The Korean
Independent
Commission against
Corruption
Public Officials Misuse of
Authority
Grant seeking -
Transparency
International
Public Officials Misuse of
Authority
Grant seeking -
If we use the perspective of deontological and
teleological ethics to read the definitions of
corruption, we that the orientation of teleological
ethics is more dominant. We see this perspective in
criteria II and III, which is detrimental to the economy
of the state and the motive to grant seeking. Whereas
the criteria I, i.e., the misuse of authority, literally, we
identify it as the deontological view that an official
must fulfill their duty and obligation. In the name of
this duty, he is prohibited from misusing the
authority.
But as we have stated above, the deontological
ethics presuppose the motive to duty. People can do
the same action, for example, being honest, but the
different motive makes a different conclusion,
whether the action is categorized as deontological or
not. If being honest by a shop seller is motivated to
attract consumer's attention, the action cannot be
categorized as deontological ethics. Only if he has a
motive to duty, that being honest is an obligation in
terms of the categorical imperative, we can categorize
the action as ethics from a deontological perspective.
If the doer is honest to attract consumer attention, we
place this action as teleological.
So, based on this requirement, practically,
deontological ethics is very difficult to be identified.
If ethical action presupposes the right motive of the
actor, our conclusion to the action is almost
impossible. We do not know the motive of the actor.
What we can see is just the action. The motive rightly
inhabits inside of the actor's heart. One action may
express a deontological action, but if the motive of
action is not to duty, the action rightly is not
deontological. On the other side, we are possible to
identify teleological actions. The measures are
tangible and very clear that we can see the criteria of
impact, whether good or bad.
In the actions categorized as corruption,
detrimental to the economy, and grant seeking is far
easier to identify than identifying the motive of the
actor to do the duty of categorical imperative. Hence,
it is easy to understand why the teleological
considerations are more applicable than
deontological in identifying corrupt actions. Even the
misuse of authority then must be connected to grant
seeking. This telos makes it easier to identify
corruption in the action of the misuse of authority.
Based on this analysis, we can see that the
teleological perspective, especially in terms of utility
impact becomes the basis in identifying corrupt
action.
The other aspect we need to underline in the
definitions of corruption is about the scope of the
actor. Generally, the actor in the definitions of
The Principle of Ethics behind the Definitions of Corruption
141
corruption concentrates on public officials. In the
definitions above, we find that The Asian
Development's definition states the private official.
Whereas in the Indonesian Act of Corruption, Crime
generally says, "Any person…" so that includes
public and private. We have seen that many private
officials have been arrested by the Corruption
Eradication Commission of the Republic of Indonesia
because of their bribery to public officials. Of course,
this is a good thing in the context of corruption
eradication.
4 CONCLUSION
Generally, the main criteria in the definitions of
corruption are about the misuse of authority by public
officials to seek grants for himself or a third party.
Almost all definitions contain this main aspect.
Another definition adds the scope of the actor and the
criteria. The Asian Development Bank and
Indonesian Act of Corruption Crime add the private
official as the term of the actor. And for the later only,
it adds the criteria of detrimental to economy and
finance of the state. Every definition, of course, arises
in the special political and social context, so that the
definition emphasizes its important problems to
solve.
In the ethical perspective, we see that most of the
definition emphasizes the teleological ethics. The
impact and consequence become the main criteria in
understanding corrupt actions. It is easy to explain
why the teleological is more dominant in the
definitions of corruption. The reason is that the
impact and consequences are practically far easier to
identify corrupt actions. The misuse of authority to
seek grant for himself or third party is easy to trace.
We also can to measure the detrimental to the
economy or finance of the state. We will be in
difficult if we must identify integrity action done by
a person, whether its motive is to act obligation in
terms of categorical imperative or not. But at the same
time, we must realize that ethical action is if we act
something because it is a good thing, without
consideration of the consequence. We must be honest
unconditionally, no matter it will have a good impact
or not. Indeed, at the practical level, it is difficult to
apply this ethical conception. Using the impact
perspective is more practical and easier in identifying
corrupt actions.
REFERENCES
Books:
Bentham, Jeremy 1823. An Introduction to the Principles of
Moral and Legislation, Oxford: The Clarendon Press.
Kant, Immanuel, 2002. Groundwork for the Metaphysics of
Morals. Edited and translated by Allen Wood. New
Haven dan London: Yale University Press.
Mill, John Stuart, 1906. Utilitarianism. Chicago: The
University of Chicago Press.
Priyono, B. Herry, 2018. Korupsi: Melacak Arti, Menyimak
Implikasi. Jakarta: Penerbit PT Gramedia Pustaka
Utama.
Sandel, Michael J., 2009. Justice: What’s the Right Thing
to Do? New York: Farrar, Straus, and Giroux
Warnock, Marry, 2003. “Introduction” in Marry Warnock
(ed.) Utilitarianism and On Liberty Including Mill’s
‘Essay on Bentham’ and selections from the writings of
Jeremy Bentham and John Austin, Second Edition,
United Kingdom: Blackwell Publishing.
Documents:
OECD 2007, Corruption: A Glossary of International
Criminal Standards, retrieved August, 6, 2019, from
http://www.oecd.org/corruption/anti-
bribery/39532693.pdf
Undang-undang Republik Indonesia Nomor 20 Tahun 2001
Tentang Perubahan atas Undang-undang Republik
Indonesia Nomor 31 Tahun 1999 Tentang
Pemberantasan Tindak Pidana Korupsi
Undang-undang Republik Indonesia Nomor 31 Tahun 1999
Tentang Pemberantasan Tindak Pidana Korupsi
United Nations 2004, United Nations Convention Against
Corruption, New York: United Nations, retrieved
August, 6, 2019, from
https://www.unodc.org/documents/brussels/UN_Conv
ention_Against_Corruption.pdf
Websites:
https://www.etymonline.com/word/corruption
https://www.etymonline.com/word/corrupt
https://www.transparency.org/glossary/term/corruption
https://www.adb.org/documents/anticorruption-policy
ICOACI 2019 - International Conference on Anti-Corruption and Integrity
142