5 CONCLUSION
Motivated by a seminar relation between the presen-
ter and participants, we settle knowledge acquisitions
and distributed knowledge base.
We established theoretical results:
(a) A triplet of a positive set, a negative set and con-
clusion as a rule, is adopted, such that a rule set may
be regarded as acquired knowledge whose evaluation
is made in 3-valued domain: The rule-set evaluation
is based on 3-valued bounded lattice structure.
(b) This evaluation involves complex difficulty caused
by strong negatives. We conclude that a fixed point of
a mapping associated with a rule set may be a model
(which evaluates the rule set as true in the 3-valued
domain). A fixed point does not always exist, how-
ever, it may be a model if it must be consistent (that
is, no case is evaluated as both positive and negative),
leaving the unknown (undefined) as it is.
(c) A retrieval derivation is made by amending nega-
tion by failure, to be sound with respect to the model
which is a consistent fixed point.
This is another theoretical dealing with the alge-
braic/logical complex, compared with the papers (Ya-
masaki and Sasakura, 2021a; Yamasaki and Sasakura,
2022). Then we deal with distributed knowledge base
containing common prevention, abstractly reflecting
the seminar system with the reports on negatives from
participants.
(d) We think of a tuple of triplets (for rule sets) as dis-
tributed knowledge base, which is regarded as a theo-
retical representation of a seminar system.
(e) The evaluation of distributed knowledge base is
made such that we may have some model by a con-
sistent fixed point of a mapping associated with dis-
tributed knowledge base, although such a fixed point
does not always exist. This mapping contains the
mappings associated with acquired knowledges (vir-
tually of participants).
(f) With some assumed prevention, distributed re-
trieval derivations are available by means of strate-
gies containing individual derivation for knowledge
as briefly pointed out in (c).
As in the treatment of communication (Yamasaki
and Sasakura, 2021b), if both positive and negative
are common, then the whole distributed knowledge
base should be treated as single knowledge base. In
this case, Section 3 gives a theoretical base. Ow-
ing to implementation of communication among R
k
(1 ≤ k ≤ n), the retrieval derivation must be essen-
tially complex. If we could have access to another R
j
from R
k
only by reference to, a possible fixed point
and the given procedural aspects of retrieval deriva-
tion may be abstractly simpler.
REFERENCES
Bentham, J. V., K.Mierzewski, and Blando, F. (2022). The
modal logic of stepwise removal. Rev.Symb.Log.,
15(1):36–63.
Cardelli, L. and Gordon, A. (2000). Mobile ambients. The-
oret.Comput.Sci., 240(1):177–213.
Christoff, Z., Gratzl, N., and Roy, O. (2022). Priority
merge and intersection modalities. Rev.Symb.Log.,
15(1):165–a96.
Egre, P., Marty, P., and Renne, B. (2021). Knowledge,
justification and adequate reasoning. Rev.Symb.Log.,
14(3):681–727.
Fitting, M. (2002). Modal logics between propositional and
first-order. J.Log.comput., 12(6):1017–1026.
Gebser, M. and Schaub, T. (2016). Modeling and language
extensions. AI Magazine, 3(3):33–44.
Goldblatt, R. and Hodkinson, I. (2020). Strong com-
pleteness of modal logics over 0-dimensional metric
spaces. Rev.Log.Comput., 13(3):611–632.
Hanks, S. and McDermott, D. (1987). Nonmonotonic logic
and temporal projection. Artifi.Intelli., 33(3):379–
412.
Hornicher, L. (2021). The logic of information in state
spaces. Rev.Symb.Log., 15(1):155–186.
Kaufmann, B., Leone, N., Perri, S., and Schaub, T. (2016).
Grounding and solving in answer set programming. AI
Magazine, 3(3):25–32.
Merro, M. and Nardelli, F. (2005). Behavioural theory for
mobile ambients. J.ACM., 52(6):961–1023.
Naumov, P. and Tao, J. (2019). Everyone knows that
some knows: Quantifiers over epistemic agents. Re-
view.Symb.Log., 12(2):255–270.
Pawlowski, P. and Urbaniak, R. (2018). Many-valued logic
of informal provability: A non-deterministic strategy.
Review.Symb.Log., 11(2):207–223.
Rasga, J., Sernadas, C., and Carnielli, W. (2021). Reduction
techniques for proving decidability in logics and their
meet-combination. Bull.Symb.Log., 27(1):39–66.
Reiter, R. (2001). Knowledge in Action. MIT Press.
Rin, B. and S.Walsh (2016). Realizability semantics for
quantified modal logic: generalizing flagg’s 1985 con-
struction. Rev.Symb.Log., 9(4):752–809.
Tennant, N. (2021). What is a rule of inference.
Rev.Symb.Log., 14(2):307–346.
Yamasaki, S. and Sasakura, M. (2021a). Algebraic expres-
sions with state constraints for causal relations and
data semantics. In CCIS 1446, Data Management
Technologies and Applications, pages 245–266.
Yamasaki, S. and Sasakura, M. (2021b). Distributed strate-
gies and managements based on state constraint logic
with predicate for communication. In Proceedings of
the 6th International Conference on Complexity, Fu-
ture Information Systems and Risk, pages 78–85.
Yamasaki, S. and Sasakura, M. (2022). Consultation to ef-
fectiveness and logical meaning. In Proceedings of
the 6th International Conference on Complexity, Fu-
ture Information Systems and Risk, pages 57–64.
COMPLEXIS 2023 - 8th International Conference on Complexity, Future Information Systems and Risk
46